•  279
    Types of Personal Identity
    Cogito 11 (2): 117-122. 1997.
    This is a paper, aimed at students, which sets out some issues regarding personal identity over time.
  •  74
    Review of Empty Ideas (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2014 (Dec 18). 2014.
    A review of Peter Unger's Empty Ideas (OUP 2014)
  •  24
    Pumped up Physicalism (review)
    Metascience 14 (2): 277-281. 2005.
    This is a review of Physicalism, by Andrew Melynyk.
  •  36
    II—Katherine Hawley: Neo-Fregeanism and Quantifier Variance
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1): 233-249. 2007.
  •  176
    N eo-F regeanism and Q uantifier V ariance
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1): 233-249. 2007.
    In his paper in the same volume, Sider argues that, of maximalism and quantifier variance, the latter promises to let us make better sense of neo-Fregeanism. I argue that neo-Fregeans should, and seemingly do, reject quantifier variance. If they must choose between these two options, they should choose maximalism.
  •  43
    The Trust Game and the Testimony Game
    Abstracta 6 (S6): 84-91. 2012.
    This is part of a symposium on Paul Faulkner's book 'Knowledge on Trust'. The symposium also includes pieces by Guy Longworth, Arnon Keren, Edward S. Hinchman, and Peter J. Graham, with précis and replies by Paul Faulkner. For a more straightforward account of the book, see my review in Philosophical Quarterly 63.1 (2013), 170-71.
  •  720
    Cut the Pie Any Way You Like? Cotnoir on General Identity
    Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 8 323-30. 2013.
    This is a short response to Aaron Cotnoir's 'Composition as General Identity', in which I suggest some further applications of his ideas, and try to press the question of why we should think of his 'general identity relation' as a genuine identity relation.
  •  139
    David Lewis on Persistence
    In Barry Loewer & Jonathan Schaffer (eds.), A Companion to David Lewis, Wiley. 2015.
    This chapter explores the connections between David Lewis's perdurance theory and his Humean supervenience, arguing that his influential argument about temporary intrinsics is best seen in this light. It presents domestic dispute within the anti‐endurantist camp and analyzes the following questions: why does Lewis identify ordinary objects with world‐bound parts of transworld objects, but not with time‐bound parts of transtemporal objects? Given that Lewis is a counterpart theorist about modalit…Read more
  •  337
    Success and Knowledge-How
    American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (1). 2003.
    In this paper, I argue that there is a notion of 'counterfactual success' which stands to knowledge how as true belief stands to propositional knowledge. (I attempt to avoid the question of whether knowledge how is a type of propositional knowledge.)
  •  252
    Persistence and non-supervenient relations
    Mind 108 (429): 53-67. 1999.
    I claim that, if persisting objects have temporal parts, then there are non-supervenient relations between those temporal parts. These are relations which are not determined by intrinsic properties of the temporal parts. I use the Kripke-Armstrong 'rotating homogeneous disc' argument in order to establish this claim, and in doing so I defend and develop that argument. This involves a discussion of instantaneous velocity, and of the causes and effects of rotation. Finally, I compare alternative r…Read more
  •  4
    Knowledge on Trust. by Paul Faulkner (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 63 (250): 170-171. 2013.
    Book review
  •  330
    What are natural kinds?1
    Philosophical Perspectives 25 (1): 205-221. 2011.
    We articulate a view of natural kinds as complex universals. We do not attempt to argue for the existence of universals. Instead, we argue that, given the existence of universals, and of natural kinds, the latter can be understood in terms of the former, and that this provides a rich, flexible framework within which to discuss issues of indeterminacy, essentialism, induction, and reduction. Along the way, we develop a 'problem of the many' for universals.
  •  438
    Identity and Indiscernibility
    Mind 118 (469): 101-119. 2009.
    Putative counterexamples to the Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles (PII) are notoriously inconclusive. I establish ground rules for debate in this area, offer a new response to such counterexamples for friends of the PII, but then argue that no response is entirely satisfactory. Finally, I undermine some positive arguments for PII
  •  42
    Review of Fourdimensionalism (review)
    Noûs 40 (2). 2006.
    This is a critical study of Ted Sider's book 'Four-Dimensionalism' . Oxford university press 2001. ISBN 0 19 924443 X, hardback; ISBN 0 19 926352 3, paperback.
  •  346
    Temporal Parts
    Stanford Encylopedia of Philosophy. 2004/2010.
    Material objects extend through space by having different spatial parts in different places. But how do they persist through time? According to some philosophers, things have temporal parts as well as spatial parts: accepting this is supposed to help us solve a whole bunch of metaphysical problems, and keep our philosophy in line with modern physics. Other philosophers disagree, arguing that neither metaphysics nor physics give us good reason to believe in temporal parts.
  •  132
    Review of The Possibility of Metaphysics (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (3): 478-482. 1999.
    A review of The Possibility of Metaphysics: substance, identity and time, by E.J. Lowe.
  •  64
    Review of Identity in Physics: A Historical, Philosophical, and Formal Analysis (review)
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 21 (1): 106-108. 2007.
    This is a short review of Identity in Physics, by Steven French and Decio Krause. (Tip: if you’re only going to read one chapter, make it chapter 4, where the philosophical juice is especially concentrated.).
  •  168
    Trivial Truthmaking Matters
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 83 (1). 2011.
    This is a contribution to a symposium on Trenton Merricks' book Truth and Ontology. The symposium includes contributions by Karen Bennett and Kris McDaniel, with précis and replies by Trenton Merricks. I argue that even the very weak truthmaking principle he is willing to endorse is nevertheless useful for some philosophical purposes.
  •  67
    ‘Fusion’ is a philosophical term of art, with a variety of uses. First, it is often a synonym for ‘sum’. In this sense, a is a fusion of b, c and d iff b, c and d are parts of a, and every part of a shares a part with b, c or d. So a cat is a fusion of the cells which compose it, and the same cat is a fusion of the molecules which compose it. Relatedly, ‘fusion’ can refer to the occurrence of such composition: philosophers disagree about whether fusion is widespread, about whether it can be a va…Read more
  •  243
    Merricks on whether being conscious is intrinsic
    Mind 107 (428): 841-843. 1998.
    This is a short response to a paper by Trenton Merricks in which he argues against the following doctrine: Microphysical Supervenience (MS) Necessarily, if atoms A1 through An compose an object that exemplifies intrinsic qualitative properties Q1 through Qn, then atoms like A1 through An (in all their respective intrinsic qualitative properties), related to one another by all the same restricted atom-to-atom relations as A1 through An, compose an object that exemplifies Q1 through Qn.
  •  283
    Testimony and knowing how
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (4): 397-404. 2010.
    Much of what we learn from talking and listening does not qualify as testimonial knowledge: we can learn a great deal from other people without simply accepting what they say as being true. In this article, I examine the ways in which we acquire skills or knowledge how from our interactions with other people, and I discuss whether there is a useful notion of testimonial knowledge how.Keywords: Knowledge how; Practical knowledge; Tacit knowledge; Testimony; Skills; Assertion.
  •  294
    Partiality and prejudice in trusting
    Synthese 191 (9). 2014.
    You can trust your friends. You should trust your friends. Not all of your friends all of the time: you can reasonably trust different friends to different degrees, and in different domains. Still, we often trust our friends, and it is often reasonable to do so. Why is this? In this paper I explore how and whether friendship gives us reasons to trust our friends, reasons which may outstrip or conflict with our epistemic reasons. In the final section, I will sketch some related questions concerni…Read more
  •  79
    Metaphysics and relativity
    In Robin Le Poidevin, Simons Peter, McGonigal Andrew & Ross P. Cameron (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics, Routledge. 2009.
    This is a very introductory introduction to some ways in which the special and general theories of relativity may bear upon metaphysical questions about the nature of time and space, and the persistence of objects.
  •  245
    Weak discernibility
    Analysis 66 (4). 2006.
    Simon Saunders argues that, although distinct objects must be discernible, they need only be weakly discernible (Saunders 2003, 2006a). I will argue that this combination of views is unmotivated: if there can be objects which differ only weakly, there can be objects which don’t differ at all.
  •  189
    Indeterminism and indeterminacy
    Analysis 58 (2): 101-106. 1998.
    E.J. Lowe claims that quantum physics provides examples of ontic indeterminacy, of vagueness in the world. Any such claim must confront the Evans-Salmon argument to the effect that the notion of ontic indeterminacy is simply incoherent (Evans 1978, Salmon 1981: 243-46). Lowe argues that a standard version of the Evans-Salmon argument fails quite generally (Lowe 1994). Harold Noonan (1995) has outlined a non-standard version of the argument, but Lowe argues that this non-standard version fails fo…Read more
  •  16
    Thomas S. Kuhn's mysterious worlds
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 27 (2): 291-300. 1996.
    An essay review of two books about Kuhn and Kuhnian ideas.
  •  200
    Borderline Simple or Extremely Simple
    The Monist 87 (3): 385-404. 2004.
    In his Material Beings, Peter van Inwagen distinguishes two questions about parthood. What are the conditions necessary and sufficient for some things jointly to compose a whole? What are the conditions necessary and sufficient for a thing to have proper parts? The first of these, the Special Composition Question (SCQ), has been widely discussed, and David Lewis has argued that an important constraint on any answer to the SCQ is that it should not permit borderline cases of composition. This is …Read more
  •  22
    Review. The possibility of metaphysics; substance, identity and time. E J Lowe (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (3): 478-482. 1999.
  •  1410
    Ontological Innocence
    In A. J. Cotnoir & Donald L. M. Baxter (eds.), Composition as Identity, Oxford University Press. pp. 70-89. 2014.
    In this chapter, I examine Lewis's ideas about ontological innocence, ontological commitment and double-counting, in his discussion of composition as identity in Parts of Classes. I attempt to understand these primarily as epistemic or methodological claims: how far can we get down this route without adopting radical metaphysical theses about composition as identity?