•  77
    Kitcher on the Ethics of Inquiry
    with Robert B. Talisse
    Journal of Social Philosophy 38 (4): 654-665. 2007.
    The thesis that scientific inquiry must operate within moral constraints is familiar and unobjectionable in cases involving immoral treatment of experimental subjects, as in the infamous Tuskegee experiments. However, in Science, Truth, and Democracy1 and related work,2 Philip Kitcher envisions a more controversial set of constraints. Specifically, he argues that inquiry ought not to be pursued in cases where the consequences of its pursuit are likely to affect negatively the lives of individuals …Read more
  •  668
    Still Searching for a Pragmatist Pluralism
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 41 (1). 2005.
    Talisse and Aikin reply to Critics
  •  111
    Two Forms of the Straw Man
    Argumentation 20 (3): 345-352. 2006.
    The authors identify and offer an analysis of a new form of the Straw Man fallacy, and then explore the implications of the prevalence of this fallacy for contemporary political discourse
  •  54
    Why We Argue: A Sketch of an Epistemic-Democratic Program
    Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 29 (2): 60-67. 2014.
    This essay summarizes the research program developed in our new book, Why We Argue (And How We Should): A Guide to Political Disagreement (Routledge, 2014). Humans naturally want to know and to take themselves as having reason on their side. Additionally, many people take democracy to be a uniquely proper mode of political arrangement. There is an old tension between reason and democracy, however, and it was first articulated by Plato. Plato’s concern about democracy was that it detached politic…Read more
  •  24
    Introduction
    Metaphilosophy 45 (2): 139-145. 2014.
    This introduction presents selected proceedings of a two-day meeting on the regress problem, sponsored by the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO) and hosted by Vanderbilt University in October 2013, along with other submitted essays. Three forms of research on the regress problem are distinguished: metatheoretical, developmental, and critical work
  •  91
    Evolution, Intelligent Design and Public Education: A Comment on Thomas Nagel
    with Michael Harbour and Robert Talisse
    Spontaneous Generations 3 (1): 35-40. 2009.
    Thomas Nagel recently proposed that the exclusion of Intelligent Design from science classrooms is inappropriate and that there needs to be room for “noncommittal discussion.” It is shown that Nagel’s policy proposals do not ?t the conclusions of his arguments
  • Replies To Our Critics
    William James Studies 6 28-34. 2011.
  •  90
    Rockmore on analytic pragmatism
    Metaphilosophy 39 (2): 155-162. 2008.
    Aikin and Talisse reply to Rockmore's case against the 'analytic pragmatist' tradition.
  •  1
    Three Challenges To Jamesian Ethics
    William James Studies 6 3-9. 2011.
    Classical pragmatism is committed to the thought that philosophy must be relevant to ordinary life. This commitment is frequently employed critically: to show that some idea is irrelevant to ordinary life is to prove it to be expendable. But the commitment is also constructive: pragmatists must strive to make their positive views relevant. Accordingly, one would expect the classical pragmatists to have fixed their attention on ethics, since this is the area of philosophy most attuned to everyday…Read more
  •  251
    Nagel on Public Education and Intelligent Design
    with Michael Harbour and Robert B. Talisse
    Journal of Philosophical Research 35 209-219. 2010.
    In a recent article, Thomas Nagel argues against the court’s decision to strike down the Dover school district’s requirement that biology teachers in Dover public schools inform their students about Intelligent Design. Nagel contends that this ruling relies on questionable demarcation between science and nonscience and consequently misapplies the Establishment Clause of the constitution. Instead, he argues in favor of making room for an open discussion of these issues rather than an outright pro…Read more
  •  48
    Politics, for God’s sake (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 54 (54): 106-107. 2011.
  •  19
    Nagel on Public Education and Intelligent Design
    with Michael Harbour and Robert B. Talisse
    Journal of Philosophical Research 35 209-219. 2010.
    In a recent article, Thomas Nagel argues against the court’s decision to strike down the Dover school district’s requirement that biology teachers in Dover public schools inform their students about Intelligent Design. Nagel contends that this ruling relies on questionable demarcation between science and nonscience and consequently misapplies the Establishment Clause of the constitution. Instead, he argues in favor of making room for an open discussion of these issues rather than an outright pro…Read more
  •  9
    Politics, for God’s sake (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 54 106-107. 2011.
  •  140
    Modus Tonens
    Argumentation 22 (4): 521-529. 2008.
    Restating an interlocutor’s position in an incredulous tone of voice can sometimes serve legitimate dialectical ends. However, there are cases in which incredulous restatement is out of bounds. This article provides an analysis of one common instance of the inappropriate use of incredulous restatement, which the authors call “modus tonens.” The authors argue that modus tonens is vicious because it pragmatically implicates the view that one’s interlocutor is one’s cognitive subordinate and provid…Read more
  •  55
    Matters of conscience (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 61 (61): 113-114. 2013.
  •  28
    On Epistemic Abstemiousness and Diachronic Norms: A Reply to Bundy
    with Michael Harbour, Jonathan Neufeld, and Robert Talisse
    Logos and Episteme 3 (1): 125-130. 2012.
    In “On Epistemic Abstemiousness,” Alex Bundy has advanced his criticism of our view that the Principle of Suspension yields serious diachronic irrationality. Here, we defend the diachronic perspective on epistemic norms and clarify how we think the diachronic consequences follow.
  •  4
    Matters of conscience (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 61 113-114. 2013.
  •  539
    Epistemic Abstainers, Epistemic Martyrs, and Epistemic Converts
    with Michael Harbour and Robert B. Talisse
    Logos and Episteme 1 (2): 211-219. 2010.
    An intuitive view regarding the epistemic significance of disagreement says that when epistemic peers disagree, they should suspend judgment. This abstemious view seems to embody a kind of detachment appropriate for rational beings; moreover, it seems to promote a kind of conciliatory inclination that makes for irenic and cooperative further discussion. Like many strategies for cooperation, however, the abstemious view creates opportunities for free-riding. In this essay, the authors argue that …Read more
  •  120
    Deep Disagreement and the Problem of the Criterion
    Topoi 40 (5): 1017-1024. 2018.
    My objective in this paper is to compare two philosophical problems, the problem of the criterion and the problem of deep disagreement, and note a core similarity which explains why many proposed solutions to these problems seem to fail along similar lines. From this observation, I propose a kind of skeptical solution to the problem of deep disagreement, and this skeptical program has consequences for the problem as it manifests in political epistemology and metaphilosophy.
  •  47
  •  14
    Comic Phthonos and Protreptic Premises
    Southwest Philosophy Review 33 (2): 35-38. 2017.
  •  25
    What did Epicurus Learn from Plato?
    Philosophy 92 (3): 421-447. 2017.
  •  25
    Methodological and Metaphilosophical Lessons in Plato's Ion
    Journal of Ancient Philosophy 11 (1): 1-19. 2017.
    From a detailed overview of Socrates’ exchange with Ion, light is shed on why Socrates’ method of elenchusrequires explicit accounts of concepts at issue. Moreover, Ion’s character is shown to provide an object lesson in the tempting vice of intellectual sycophancy.
  •  22
  •  13
    Fallacy theory has three significant challenges to it: the generality, scope, and negativity problems. To the generality problem, the connection between general types of bad arguments and tokens is a matter of refining the use of the vocabulary. To the scope problem, the breadth of fallacy’s instances is cause for development. To the negativity problem, fallacy theory must be coordinated with a program of adversariality-management.
  •  66
    Democratic Deliberation, Public Reason, and Environmental Politics
    Environmental Philosophy 3 (2): 52-58. 2006.
    The activity of democratic deliberation is governed by the norm of public reason – namely, that reasons justifying public policy must both be pursuant of shared goods and be shareable by all reasonable discussants. Environmental policies based on controversial theories of value, as a consequence, are in danger of breaking the rule that would legitimate their enforcement.