•  43
    Pregnant Premise Arguments
    Informal Logic 32 (3): 357-363. 2012.
  •  156
    Skeptical Theism, Moral Skepticism, and Divine Commands
    International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 3 (2): 77-96. 2013.
    Over the last twenty-five years skeptical theism has become one of the leading contemporary responses to the atheological argument from evil. However, more recently, some critics of skeptical theism have argued that the skeptical theists are in fact unwittingly committed to a malignant form of moral skepticism. Several skeptical theists have responded to this critique by appealing to divine commands as a bulwark against the alleged threat of moral skepticism. In this paper we argue that the skep…Read more
  •  88
    A defense of war and sport metaphors in argument
    Philosophy and Rhetoric 44 (3): 250-272. 2011.
    There is a widely held concern that using war and sport metaphors to describe argument contributes to the breakdown of argumentative processes. The thumbnail version of this worry about such metaphors is that they promote adversarial conceptions of argument that lead interlocutors with those conceptions to behave adversarially in argumentative contexts. These actions are often aggressive, which undermines argument exchange by either excluding many from such exchanges or turning exchanges more in…Read more
  •  24
    Modest (but not Self-Effacing) Transcendental Arguments
    Southwest Philosophy Review 31 (1): 69-79. 2015.
  •  434
    John Dewey's Quest for unity: The journey of a promethean mystic (review) (review)
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 46 (4): 656-659. 2010.
    There is what should be called the Curious George Model of Analysis, wherein the internal conflicts of some protagonist or program are the most revealing and significant features of the story. Take George. He is a good little monkey, but he's curious. These are virtues of sorts, but George's curiosity drives him first to investigate a yellow hat, then to try to fly like the seagulls, to investigate the telephone, and finally to try holding a large bunch of balloons. In each case, these actions d…Read more
  •  164
    Wittgenstein, Dewey, and the possibility of religion
    Journal of Speculative Philosophy 20 (1): 1-19. 2006.
    John Dewey points out in A Common Faith (1934) that what stands in the way of religious belief for many is the apparent commitment of Western religious traditions to supernatural phenomena and questionable historical claims. We are to accept claims that in any other context we would find laughable. Are we to believe that water can be turned into wine without the benefit of the fermentation process? Are we to swallow the claim that there is such a phenomenon as the spontaneous conception of a chi…Read more
  •  200
    In the last decade, the familiar problem of the regress of reasons has returned to prominent consideration in epistemology. And with the return of the problem, evaluation of the options available for its solution is begun anew. Reason’s regress problem, roughly put, is that if one has good reasons to believe something, one must have good reason to hold those reasons are good. And for those reasons, one must have further reasons to hold they are good, and so a regress of reasons looms. In this ne…Read more
  • The Ethics of Inquiry and Engagement: The Case of Science in Public
    with Michael Harbour
    Public Affairs Quarterly 24 (2): 155-168. 2010.
    There has been a promising discussion brewing recently about whether there is an ethics of inquiry—that is, a unique set of ethical rules that constrains inquirers specifically in their role as inquirers. Most prominently, Philip Kitcher has proposed that there is indeed an ethics of inquiry. He argues that, given the intellectual climate of many modern societies, certain research programs are likely to encourage further social injustice against members of already disadvantaged groups; in such c…Read more