•  166
    17. Will and the Theory of Judgment
    In Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (ed.), Essays on Descartes’ Meditations, University of California Press. pp. 405-434. 1986.
    Contemporary discussions typically give somewhat sort shrift to the theory of judgment Descartes advances in the Fourth Meditation.' One reason for this relative neglect is presumably the prima facie implausibility of the theory. It sounds odd to say that, in believing something, one's mental affirmation is an act of free will, on a par with freely deciding what to do. In addition, Descartes advances the theory as a way to explain the possibility of human error, which doubtless strikes many as a…Read more
  •  845
    Higher-Order Awareness, Misrepresentation, and Function
    Higher-Order Awareness, Misrepresentation and Function 367 (1594): 1424-1438. 2012.
    Conscious mental states are states we are in some way aware of. I compare higher-order theories of consciousness, which explain consciousness by appeal to such higher-order awareness (HOA), and first-order theories, which do not, and I argue that higher-order theories have substantial explanatory advantages. The higher-order nature of our awareness of our conscious states suggests an analogy with the metacognition that figures in the regulation of psychological processes and behaviour. I argue…Read more
  •  114
    The Rosenthal-Sellars correspondence on intentionality
    with Wilfrid S. Sellars
    In Ausonio Marras (ed.), Intentionality, Mind, And Language, University of Illinois Press. 1972.
    In response to your kind offer to read through portions of the typescript of my thesis pertaining to your views on intentionality, I am sending you a copy of an introductory section to such a chapter.{1} The enclosed typescript represents a first draft, for which I apologize, but I thought it might be useful to get any comments you might have in at the ground floor, so to speak
  •  2
    Emotions and the self
    In K. Irani & Gerald E. Myers (eds.), Emotion: Philosophical Studies, Haven. 1983.
    Much of the perplexity that motivates modern discussion of the nature of mind derives indirectly from the striking success of physical explanation. Not only has physics itself advanced at a remarkable pace in the last four centuries; every hope has been held out that, in principle, all science can be understood and ultimately studied in terms of mechanisms proper to physics. Seeing all natural phenomena as explicable in terms appropriate to physics, however, makes the mental seem to be a singula…Read more
  •  30
    Keeping matter in mind
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1): 295-322. 1980.
  •  31
    Time and consciousness
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2): 220-221. 1992.
  •  135
    PowerPoint presentation at Tucson VII, Toward a Science of Consciousness 2006, session on Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness.
  •  404
    How to think about mental qualities
    Philosophical Issues 20 (1): 368-393. 2010.
    It’s often held that undetectable inversion of mental qualities is, if not possible, at least conceivable. It’s thought to be conceivable that the mental quality your visual states exhibit when you see something red in standard conditions is literally of the same type as the mental quality my visual states exhibit when I see something green in such circumstances. It’s thought, moreover, to be conceivable that such inversion of mental qualities could be wholly undetectable by any third-person mea…Read more
  •  153
    Being conscious of ourselves
    The Monist 87 (2): 161-184. 2004.
    What is it that we are conscious of when we are conscious of ourselves? Hume famously despaired of finding self, as against simply finding various impressions and ideas, when, as he put it, “I enter most intimately into what I call myself.” “When I turn my reflexion on myself, I never can perceive this self without some one or more perceptions; nor can I ever perceive any thing but the perceptions.”
  •  1
    Reductionism and knowledge
    In L. S. Cauman, Isaac Levi, Charles D. Parsons & Robert Schwartz (eds.), How Many Questions?, Hacket. 1983.
  •  514
    The Higher-Order Model of Consciousness
    In Rita Carter (ed.), Consciousness, Weidenfeld & Nicolson. 2002.
    All mental states, including thoughts, feelings, perceptions, and sensations, often occur consciously. But they all occur also without being conscious. So the first thing a theory of consciousness must do is explain the difference between thoughts, feelings, perceptions, and sensations that are conscious and those which are not.
  •  23
    Unity Of Consciousness And The Self
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (3): 325-352. 2003.
  •  508
    Consciousness, the self and bodily location
    Analysis 70 (2): 270-276. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  139
    Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem (edited book)
    Prentice-Hall. 1971.
    An expanded and updated edition of this classic collection
  •  736
    Two concepts of consciousness
    Philosophical Studies 49 (May): 329-59. 1986.
    No mental phenomenon is more central than consciousness to an adequate understanding of the mind. Nor does any mental phenomenon seem more stubbornly to resist theoretical treatment. Consciousness is so basic to the way we think about the mind that it can be tempting to suppose that no mental states exist that are not conscious states. Indeed, it may even seem mysterious what sort of thing a mental state might be if it is not a conscious state. On this way of looking at things, if any mental sta…Read more
  •  150
    Consciousness and the mind
    Jerusalem Philosophical Quarterly 51 (July): 227-251. 2002.
    Everyone — or almost everyone — was agreed that what is [mental] … has a common quality in which its essence is expressed: namely the quality of being conscious — unique, indescribable, but needing no description. All that is conscious … is [mental], and conversely all that is [mental] is conscious; that is self-evident and to contradict it is nonsense
  •  17
    Introspection and Self-Interpretation
    Philosophical Topics 28 (2): 201-233. 2000.
  •  688
    in Encyclopedia of Consciousness, ed. William P. Banks, Amsterdam: Elsevier, forthcoming in 2009
  •  442
    How many kinds of consciousness?
    Consciousness and Cognition 11 (4): 653-665. 2002.
    Ned BlockÕs influential distinction between phenomenal and access consciousness has become a staple of current discussions of consciousness. It is not often noted, however, that his distinction tacitly embodies unargued theoretical assumptions that favor some theoretical treatments at the expense of others. This is equally so for his less widely discussed distinction between phenomenal consciousness and what he calls reflexive consciousness. I argue that the distinction between phenomenal and acce…Read more
  •  155
    (not intended for publication), Replies to Strawson and Block in Colloquium at the CUNY Graduate Center, December 13, 2006.
  •  198
    The main goal of Deborah Modrak's penetrating and compelling discussion is to show that Aristotle subscribed "to an integrated model of perceptual and noetic functions" (268). Using Aristotle's phrase (Γ4, 429b13, 21), Modrak describes the integrated model as the view that "the noetic faculty is the perceptual faculty differently disposed" (283). She notes that this interpretation faces certain difficulties, but argues forcefully and incisively that it can nonetheless be sustained.