•  13
    John Donne, poet laureate of the human body, was much troubled by its fate. Scorning Plato's picture of the body as the soul's prison, Donne imagined souls as leaving their bodies reluctantly and as yearning to return to the very one from which they had departed. In poems like “The Ecstasy,” he depicts the union of lovers’ souls, hints at a similar love of souls for bodies, and suggests that it is through the body—“his book”—that the lover comes to know love's spiritual mysteries. John Lantos al…Read more
  •  1
    What Do We Know When We Know How to Go On?
    Hastings Center Report 31 (4): 50-51. 2001.
  •  5
    The Social (De)Construction of Futility
    Hastings Center Report 30 (3): 49-50. 2000.
  •  18
    On the usual account of moral reasoning, social science is often seen as able to provide “just the facts,” while philosophy attends to moral values and conceptual clarity and builds formally valid arguments. Yet disciplines are informed by epistemic values—and bioethics might do well to see social scientific practices and their attendant normative understandings about what is humanly important as a significant part of ethics generally.
  •  21
    The Best Laid Plans
    with Ellen H. Moskowitz
    Hastings Center Report 25 (6): 3-5. 1995.
  •  7
    Is It Ever Right to Do Wrong? (review)
    Hastings Center Report 25 (3): 48-49. 2012.
  •  13
    Preferences and Other Moral Sources
    with Hilde Lindemann Nelson
    Hastings Center Report 24 (6): 19-21. 1994.
  •  23
    Bioethics Education
    with Barbara C. Thornton and Daniel Callahan
    Hastings Center Report 23 (1): 25-29. 1993.
    Bioethics education now takes place outside universities as well as within them. How should clinicians, ethics committee members, and policymakers be taught the ethics they need, and how may their progress best be evaluated?
  •  27
    Taking Families Seriously
    Hastings Center Report 22 (4): 6-12. 1992.
    Medical decisionmaking would be a messier but better thing if it honored what is morally valuable about patients' families. The concerns of intimates have a legitimate call upon us even when we are ill.
  •  15
    Transplantation through a Glass Darkly
    Hastings Center Report 22 (5): 6-8. 1992.
    Should baboons become spare parts bins for human beings? Not when their moral nature remains a mystery to us.
  •  5
    What Has History to Do with Me?
    Hastings Center Report 21 (4): 2-2. 1991.
  •  11
    From Chance to Choice: Genetics and Justice (review)
    with Hilde Lindemann Nelson
    American Journal of Bioethics 1 (2): 70-72. 2001.
  •  39
    Still Quiet After All These Years: Revisiting “The Silence of the Bioethicists”
    Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 9 (3): 249-259. 2012.
    Some 14 years ago, I published an article in which I identified a prime site for bioethicists to ply their trade: medical responses to requests for hormonal and surgical interventions aimed at facilitating transgendered people’s transition to their desired genders. Deep issues about the impact of biotechnologies and health care practices on central aspects of our conceptual system, I argued, were raised by how doctors understood and responded to people seeking medical assistance in changing thei…Read more
  •  35
    In this paper, I consider what kind of normative work might be done by speaking of ecosystems utilising a 'medical' vocabulary – drawing, that is, on such notions as 'health', 'disease', and 'illness'. Some writers attracted to this mode of expression have been rather modest about what they think it might purchase. I wish to be bolder. Drawing on the idea of 'thick' evaluative concepts as discussed by McDowell, Williams and Taylor, and resorting to a phenomenological argument for a kind of moral…Read more
  •  54
    Quality of care: a preface (review)
    Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 33 (4): 237-242. 2012.
  •  60
    Most people accept that if they can save someone from death at very little cost to themselves, they must do so; call this the ‘duty of easy rescue.’ At least for many such people, an instance of this duty is to allow their vital organs to be used for transplantation. Accordingly, ‘opt-out’ organ procurement policies, based on a powerfully motivated responsibility to render costless or very low-cost lifesaving aid, would seem presumptively permissible. Counterarguments abound. Here I consider, in…Read more
  •  50
    A Comment on Fry's "The Role of Caring in a Theory of Nursing Ethics"
    with Jeannine Ross Boyer
    Hypatia 5 (3): 153-158. 1990.
    Our response to Sara Fry's paper focuses on the difficulty of understanding her insistence on the fundamental character of caring in a theory of nursing ethics. We discuss a number of problems her text throws in the way of making sense of this idea, and outline our own proposal for how caring's role may be reasonably understood: not as an alternative object of value, competing with autonomy or patient good, but rather as an alternative way of responding toward that which is of value
  •  10
    Ethical Formation
    International Philosophical Quarterly 42 (4): 556-558. 2002.
  •  28
    Feminism, Social Policy, and Long-Acting Contraception
    with Hilde Lindemann Nelson
    Hastings Center Report 25 (1): 30-32. 1995.
  •  28
    Roughly thirty years ago, R. M. Hare told an Anglo-French philosophy conference about a young Swiss student who came to stay with his family in Oxford. It seems that the student was doing very nicely, until, in a burst of misguided hospitality, the Hares provided him with one of their few French books, Camus's L'Etranger. Reading Camus had the effect of changing the student from an affable, altogether attractive young man into a chain-smoking recluse for whom “rien, rien n'avait d'importance”.
  •  45
    Alzheimer's disease and socially extended mentation
    Metaphilosophy 40 (3-4): 462-474. 2009.
    The leading accounts of the ethics of proxy decision making implicitly draw on internalist conceptions of the philosophy of mind, or so this essay tries to demonstrate. Using the views of Ronald Dworkin as its jumping‐off point, the essay argues that accepting the sort of externalism associated with writers such as Putnam and Burge would alter Dworkin's conclusions concerning how we should respond to the current or precedent decisions of people suffering from dementia. Building on the views of A…Read more
  •  9
    Illusions about Persons
    American Journal of Bioethics 7 (1): 65-66. 2007.
  •  28
    Hypotheticals, Analogies, Death's Harms, and Organ Procurement
    American Journal of Bioethics 9 (8): 14-16. 2009.
    No abstract
  •  15
    Bioethics As Several Kinds of Writing
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 24 (2): 148-163. 1999.
    Three different models are described of the relationship of bioethics to the press. The first two are familiar: bioethicists often are interviewed by journalists seeking background and short quotes to insert in a story; alternately, bioethicists sometimes themselves act as journalists of a sort, writing op-eds, articles or even longer works designed for wide readership. These models share the notion that bioethicists can provide information and ideas that increase the quality of people's thinkin…Read more
  •  15
    Critical Interests and Sources of Familial Decision-Making Authority for Incapacitated Patients
    Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 23 (2): 143-148. 1995.
    How ought we to understand the sources and limits of the authority of family members to make health care decisions for their decisionally incapacitated relatives? This question is becoming increasingly crucial as the population ages and the power of medical technology waxes. It is also becoming increasingly contested, as faith in advance directives shows signs of waning, and the moral complexities of intimate relationship become more theoretically patent.This last point—the newly visible moral r…Read more
  •  43
    Synecdoche and Stigma
    Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 16 (4): 475. 2007.
    In the portion of their reply directed to me, Professor Asch and Dr. Wasserman helpfully develop the synecdoche argument by highlighting its connections to stigma. I understand them to distinguish the situation of a woman making a decision concerning her pregnancy informed by prenatal testing from a woman making a similar decision informed by considerations of, for example, poverty, like so: In testing contexts, it will characteristically be the case that the woman's decision will be distorted b…Read more
  •  31
    Partialism and parenthood
    Journal of Social Philosophy 21 (1): 107-118. 1990.
  •  24
    Publicity and pricelessness: Grassroots decisionmaking and justice in rationing
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 19 (4): 333-342. 1994.
    The "grassroots turn" in bioethical discussions about justice in allocation of health care resources has attracted a great deal of support; in the absence of a convincing theory of justice in rationing, democratic decisionmaking concerning priority setting emerges with a kind of inevitability. Yet there remain suspicions about this approach – most importantly, worries about the socially corrosive impact of explicit, public decisionmaking that in effect sets a price on the lives of persons. These…Read more