•  154
    How do we know how?
    Philosophical Explorations 11 (1). 2007.
    I raise some doubts about the plausibility of Stanley and Williamson's view that all knowledge-how is just a species of propositional knowledge. By tackling the question of what is involved in entertaining a proposition, I try to show that Stanley and Williamson's position leads to an uncomfortable dilemma. Depending on how we understand the notion of contemplating a proposition, either intuitively central cases of knowing-how cannot be thus classified or we lose our grip on the very idea of pro…Read more
  •  56
    Causal efficacy, content and levels of explanation
    Logique Et Analyse 34 (September-December): 297-318. 1991.
    Let’s consider the following paradox (Fodor [1989], Jackson and Petit [1988] [1992], Drestke [1988], Block [1991], Lepore and Loewer [1987], Lewis [1986], Segal and Sober [1991]): i) The intentional content of a thought (or any other intentional state) is causally relevant to its behavioural (and other) effects. ii) Intentional content is nothing but the meaning of internal representations. But, iii) Internal processors are only sensitive to the syntactic structures of internal representations, …Read more
  •  140
    Twin Pleas
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4): 871-889. 1997.
    Dual factor theories of meaning are fatally flawed in at least two ways. First. their very duality constitutes a problem: the two dimensions of meaning (reference and conceptual role) cannot be treated as totally orthogonal without compromising the intuition that much of our linguistic and non linguistic behavior is based on the cognizer’s interaction with the world. Second, Conceptual Role Semantics is not adequate for explaining a crucial feature of linguistic representation, viz., the special…Read more
  •  15
    First Published in 1998. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company
  •  232
    Ruritania and ecology
    Philosophical Issues 6 188-195. 1995.
    Ned Block has argued for the truth of the following conditional: If there is such a thing as narrow content, it is holistic. This paper addresses and criticises this claim.
  •  173
    Meaning, dispositions, and normativity
    Minds and Machines 9 (3): 399-413. 1999.
    In a recent paper, Paul Coates defends a sophisticated dispositional account which allegedly resolves the sceptical paradox developed by Kripke in his monograph on Wittgenstein's treatment of following a rule (Kripke, 1982). Coates' account appeals to a notion of 'homeostasis', unpacked as a subject's second-order disposition to maintain a consistent pattern of extended first-order dispositions regarding her linguistic behavior. This kind of account, Coates contends, provides a naturalistic mode…Read more
  •  102
    Ecological content
    Pragmatics and Cognition 5 (2): 253-281. 1997.
    The paper has a negative and a positive side. The negative side argues that the classical notions of narrow and wide content are not suitable for the purposes of psychological explanation. The positive side shows how to characterize an alternative notion of content that is suitable for those purposes. This account is supported by a way of conceptualizing computation that is constitutively dependent upon properties external to the system and empirical research in developmental psychology. My main…Read more
  •  140
    What We Do When We Judge
    Dialectica 65 (3): 345-367. 2011.
    In this paper I argue on two fronts. First, I press for the view that judging is a type of mental action, as opposed to those who think that judging is involuntary and hence not an action. Second, I argue that judging is specifically a type of non-voluntary mental action. My account of the non-voluntary nature of the mental act of judging differs, however, from standard non-voluntarist views, according to which ‘non-voluntary’ just means regulated by epistemic reasons. In addition, judging is no…Read more
  •  58
    Social Vision: Breaking a Philosophical Impasse?
    Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (4): 611-615. 2015.
    I argue that findings in support of Adams and Kveraga’s functional forecast model of emotion expression processing help settle the debate between rich and sparse views of the content of perceptual experience. In particular, I argue that these results in social vision suggest that the distinctive phenomenal character of experiences involving high-level properties such as emotions and social traits is best explained by their being visually experienced as opposed to being brought about by perceptua…Read more
  •  5
    Review of Language in the World. A Philosophical Enquiry. Max J. Cresswell (review)
    with Valerie Gray Hardcastle, Richard Wyatt, William S. Robinson, Matthew Elton, Austen Clark, Berent Enç, and James L. Pate
    Philosophical Psychology 9 (1): 111-140. 1996.
    Left brain‐right brain differences: inquiries, evidence, and new approaches, James F. Iaccino. Hillsdale, NH: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1993. ISBN 0–8058–1340–3Artificial intelligence: a philosophical introduction, Jack Copeland Oxford: Blackwell, 1993 ISBN 0–631–18384–1Shadows of the mind, Roger Penrose. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994. ISBN 019–8539789Raw feeling: a philosophical account of the essence of consciousness, R. Kirk. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994. ISBN 0–19–824081–3Vision:…Read more
  •  193
    Nonconceptual content
    Philosophy Compass 2 (3). 2007.
    Nonconceptualists maintain that there are ways of representing the world that do not reflect the concepts a creature possesses. They claim that the content of these representational states is genuine content because it is subject to correctness conditions, but it is nonconceptual because the creature to which we attribute it need not possess any of the concepts involved in the specification of that content. Appeals to nonconceptual content have seemed especially useful in attempts to capture the…Read more
  •  110
    Implicit conception of implicit conceptions
    Philosophical Issues 9 115-120. 1998.
    A commentary on Peacocke's notion of implicit conceptions.
  •  75
    Compositionality, iconicity, and perceptual nonconceptualism
    Philosophical Psychology 24 (2): 177-193. 2011.
    This paper concerns the role of the structural properties of representations in determining the nature of their content. I take as a starting point Fodor's (2007) and Heck's (2007) recent arguments making the iconic structure of perceptual representations essential in establishing their content as content of a different (nonconceptual) kind. I argue that the prima facie state–content error this strategy seems to display is nothing but a case of “state–content error error,” i.e., the mistake of c…Read more
  •  17
    Una crítica al realismo desde la teoría del significado
    Revista de Filosofía (Madrid) 5 13. 1991.
    A Dummett's based critic of metaphysical realism based on semantic considerations pertaining to bivalence.
  •  19
    This volume traces the modern critical and performance history of this play, one of Shakespeare's most-loved and most-performed comedies. The essay focus on such modern concerns as feminism, deconstruction, textual theory, and queer theory.
  •  183
    Semantic responsibility
    Philosophical Explorations 5 (1): 39-58. 2002.
    In this paper I attempt to develop a notion of responsibility (semantic responsibility) that is to the notion of belief what epistemic responsibility is to the notion of justification. 'Being semantically responsible' is shown to involve the fulfilment of cognitive duties which allow the agent to engage in the kind of reason-laden discourses which render her beliefs appropriately sensitive to correction. The concept of semantic responsibility suggests that the notion of belief found in contempor…Read more
  •  16
    Modularity, Relativism, and Neural Constructivism
    Cognitive Science Quarterly 2 (1): 93-106. 2002.
    Fodor claims that the modularity of mind helps undermine relativism in various forms. I shall show first, that the modular vision of mind provides insufficient support for the rejection of relativism, and second, that an alternative model may, in fact, provide a better empirical response to the relativist challenge.
  •  27
    Extruding Intentionality from the Metaphysical Flux
    Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Ai 11 501-518. 1999.
    On the Origin of Objects is, at heart, an extended search for a non-circular and nonreductive characterization of two key notions: intentionality and computation. Only a non-circular and non-reductive account of these key notions can, Smith believes, provide a secure platform for a proper understanding of the mind. The project has both a negative and a positive aspect. Negatively, Smith rejects views that attempt to identify the key notions with lower-level physical properties, arguing instead f…Read more
  •  28
    Mind and Supermind? Keith Frankish (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 57 (226): 139-142. 2007.
    This is a review of Mind and Supermind. By KEITH FRANKISH. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Pp xiv + 255. Price £45.00 (US $75.00). ISBN 0521 812038 (hardback).
  •  10
    The Future of the Cognitive Revolution (review)
    Dialogue 39 (1): 183-185. 2000.
    One common factor underlying the set of disciplines clustered together under the label of Cognitive Science is a computational model of the mind. Cognitive capacities are to be treated as information-processing operations and to be characterized in computational terms. Computational processes are defined, in turn, in terms of operations on representations. For a few years, one of the most important debates in Cognitive Science has been whether the class of mechanisms to which cognizers belong an…Read more
  •  45
    O'Regan and Noe present a wonderfully detailed and comprehensive defense of a position whose broad outline we absolutely and unreservedly endorse. They are right, it seems to us, to stress the intimacy of conscious content and embodied action, and to counter the idea of a Grand Illusion with the image of an agent genuinely in touch, via active exploration, with the rich and varied visual scene. This is an enormously impressive achievement, and we hope that the comments that follow will be.
  •  81
    Perceptual experience and its contents
    Journal of Mind and Behavior 23 (4): 375-392. 2002.
    The contents of perceptual experience, it has been argued, often include a characteristic “non-conceptual” component (Evans, 1982). Rejecting such views, McDowell (1994) claims that such contents are conceptual in every respect. It will be shown that this debate is compromised by the failure of both sides to mark a further, and crucial, distinction in cognitive space. This is the distinction between what is doubted here as mindful and mindless modes of perceiving: a distinction which cross-class…Read more