•  56
    Causal efficacy, content and levels of explanation
    Logique Et Analyse 34 (September-December): 297-318. 1991.
    Let’s consider the following paradox (Fodor [1989], Jackson and Petit [1988] [1992], Drestke [1988], Block [1991], Lepore and Loewer [1987], Lewis [1986], Segal and Sober [1991]): i) The intentional content of a thought (or any other intentional state) is causally relevant to its behavioural (and other) effects. ii) Intentional content is nothing but the meaning of internal representations. But, iii) Internal processors are only sensitive to the syntactic structures of internal representations, …Read more
  •  45
    O'Regan and Noe present a wonderfully detailed and comprehensive defense of a position whose broad outline we absolutely and unreservedly endorse. They are right, it seems to us, to stress the intimacy of conscious content and embodied action, and to counter the idea of a Grand Illusion with the image of an agent genuinely in touch, via active exploration, with the rich and varied visual scene. This is an enormously impressive achievement, and we hope that the comments that follow will be.
  •  37
    Summarizes and illuminates two decades of research Gathering important papers by both philosophers and scientists, this collection illuminates the central themes that have arisen during the last two decades of work on the conceptual foundations of artificial intelligence and cognitive science. Each volume begins with a comprehensive introduction that places the coverage in a broader perspective and links it with material in the companion volumes. The collection is of interest in many disciplines…Read more
  •  28
    Mind and Supermind? Keith Frankish (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 57 (226): 139-142. 2007.
    This is a review of Mind and Supermind. By KEITH FRANKISH. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Pp xiv + 255. Price £45.00 (US $75.00). ISBN 0521 812038 (hardback).
  •  28
    Naturalism and Causal Explanation
    Communication and Cognition: An Interdisciplinary Quarterly Journal 32 (3/4): 243-268. 1999.
    Semantic properties are not commonly held to be part of the basic ontological furniture of the world. Consequently, we confront a problem: how to 'naturalize' semantics so as to reveal these properties in their true ontological colors? Dominant naturalistic theories address semantic properties as properties of some other kind. The reductionistic flavor is unmistakable. The following quote from Fodor's Psychosemantics is probably the contemporary locus classicus of this trend. Fodor is commendabl…Read more
  •  28
    Pulp Naturalism
    Il Cannocchiale, Rivista di Studi Filosofici 2 185-195. 1997.
    There is a compelling idea in the air. Both contemporary philosophers of mind and philosophers of language are engaged in developing theories of content that are naturalistic. The stand has been taken: semantic properties are not part of the primitive ontological furniture of the world. If we want to vindicate those properties as real, we will have to show that it is possible to unpack them into some other –primitive– set of properties. It is taken for granted that there is no alternative way of…Read more
  •  28
    Why there still has to be a theory of consciousness
    Consciousness and Cognition 2 (1): 28-47. 1993.
    "Consciousness", it is widely agreed, does not name any single cognitive phenomenon. But nor is the gathering of distinct phenomena under that single label an accident. What seems to unify the range of cognitive goods in this "variety store" is the central yet elusive notion of the availability of some content or feeling in subjective experience. The paper begins by building a rough taxonomy of the various ways different approaches have tried to give an account of this central target. Among thes…Read more
  •  27
    Positing a Space Mirror Mechanism Intentional Understanding Without Action?
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 20 (5-6): 5-6. 2013.
    Recent evidence regarding a novel functionality of the mirror neuron system , a so-called 'space mirror mechanism', seems to reinforce the central role of the MNS in social cognition. According to the space mirror hypothesis, neural mirroring accounts for understanding not just what an observed agent is doing, but also the range of potential actions that a suitably located object affords an observed agent in the absence of any motor behaviour. This paper aims to show that the advocate of this sp…Read more
  •  26
    Extruding Intentionality from the Metaphysical Flux
    Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Ai 11 501-518. 1999.
    On the Origin of Objects is, at heart, an extended search for a non-circular and nonreductive characterization of two key notions: intentionality and computation. Only a non-circular and non-reductive account of these key notions can, Smith believes, provide a secure platform for a proper understanding of the mind. The project has both a negative and a positive aspect. Negatively, Smith rejects views that attempt to identify the key notions with lower-level physical properties, arguing instead f…Read more
  •  21
    Peacocke's characterization of what he calls implicit conceptions recognizes the significance of a subset of contentful states in making rational behavior intelligible. What Peacocke has to offer in this paper is an account of why we need implicit conceptions; how we can discover them; what they explain; what they are; and how they can help us to better understand some issues in the theory of meaning and the theory of knowledge. The rationalist tradition in which Peacocke's project ought to be l…Read more
  •  19
    This volume traces the modern critical and performance history of this play, one of Shakespeare's most-loved and most-performed comedies. The essay focus on such modern concerns as feminism, deconstruction, textual theory, and queer theory.
  •  19
    Mind and Supermind
    Philosophical Quarterly 57 (226): 139-142. 2007.
    This is a review of Mind and Supermind. By KEITH FRANKISH. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Pp xiv + 255. Price £45.00 (US $75.00). ISBN 0521 812038 (hardback).
  •  19
    The animal concepts debate: a metaphilosophical take
    Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 29 (2): 11-24. 2010.
    In this paper I approach the debate over non-human animals’ concepts from a metaphilosophical perspective. I compare exemplars of a full-fledged and an austere view of concepts and concept possession. A deflationist response to these views main- tains that the austere and the full-fledged theorist each makes claims that are true when they, respectively, assert and deny ‘nonhuman animals have concepts’. I will argue that the deflationist response is misplaced, using an analogy with the debate ov…Read more
  •  17
    Una crítica al realismo desde la teoría del significado
    Revista de Filosofía (Madrid) 5 13. 1991.
    A Dummett's based critic of metaphysical realism based on semantic considerations pertaining to bivalence.
  •  16
    Modularity, Relativism, and Neural Constructivism
    Cognitive Science Quarterly 2 (1): 93-106. 2002.
    Fodor claims that the modularity of mind helps undermine relativism in various forms. I shall show first, that the modular vision of mind provides insufficient support for the rejection of relativism, and second, that an alternative model may, in fact, provide a better empirical response to the relativist challenge.
  •  16
    Opacity, Know-How States, and their Content
    Disputatio 7 (40): 61-83. 2015.
    The main goal of this paper is to defend the thesis that the content of know-how states is an accuracy assessable type of nonconceptual content. My argument proceeds in two stages. I argue, first, that the intellectualist distinction between types of ways of grasping the same kind of content is uninformative unless it is tied in with a distinction between kinds of contents. Second, I consider and reject the objection that, if the content of know-how states is non-conceptual, it will be mysteriou…Read more
  •  14
    The Implicit Conception of Implicit Conceptions
    Philosophical Issues 9 115-120. 1998.
    Peacocke's characterization of what he calls implicit conceptions recognizes the significance of a subset of contentful states in making rational behavior intelligible. What Peacocke has to offer in this paper is an account of (i) why we need implicit conceptions; (ii) how we can discover them; (iii) what they explain; (iv) what they are; and (v) how they can help us to better understand some issues in the theory of meaning and the theory of knowledge. The rationalist tradition in which Peacocke…Read more
  •  11
    First Published in 1998. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company
  •  8
    The Future of the Cognitive Revolution (review)
    Dialogue 39 (1): 183-185. 2000.
    One common factor underlying the set of disciplines clustered together under the label of Cognitive Science is a computational model of the mind. Cognitive capacities are to be treated as information-processing operations and to be characterized in computational terms. Computational processes are defined, in turn, in terms of operations on representations. For a few years, one of the most important debates in Cognitive Science has been whether the class of mechanisms to which cognizers belong an…Read more
  •  7
  •  5
    Review of Language in the World. A Philosophical Enquiry. Max J. Cresswell (review)
    with Valerie Gray Hardcastle, Richard Wyatt, William S. Robinson, Matthew Elton, Austen Clark, Berent Enç, and James L. Pate
    Philosophical Psychology 9 (1): 111-140. 1996.
    Left brain‐right brain differences: inquiries, evidence, and new approaches, James F. Iaccino. Hillsdale, NH: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1993. ISBN 0–8058–1340–3Artificial intelligence: a philosophical introduction, Jack Copeland Oxford: Blackwell, 1993 ISBN 0–631–18384–1Shadows of the mind, Roger Penrose. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994. ISBN 019–8539789Raw feeling: a philosophical account of the essence of consciousness, R. Kirk. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994. ISBN 0–19–824081–3Vision:…Read more
  • Perceptual experience and its contents
    Journal of Mind and Behavior 23 (4): 375-392. 2002.