•  21
    Language, Belief and Human Beings
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 53 141-157. 2003.
    We may think of the core of Cartesian dualism as being the thesis that each of us is essentially a non-material mind or soul: ‘non-material’ in the sense that it has no weight, cannot be seen or touched, and could in principle continue to exist independently of the existence of any material thing. That idea was, of course, of enormous importance to Descartes himself, and we may feel that having rejected it, as most philosophers now have, we have rejected what is of greatest philosophical signifi…Read more
  •  30
    The Mind, the Brain and the Face
    Philosophy 60 (234): 477-493. 1985.
    ‘Only of a living human being and what resembles a living human being can one say: it has sensations; it sees; is blind; hears, is deaf; is conscious or unconscious’. 1 ‘The human body is the best picture of the human soul’. Anyone who believes that Wittgenstein's remarks here embody important truths has quite a bit of explaining to do. What needs to be explained is why it is that enormous numbers of people, people who have never had the chance to be corrupted by reading Descartes or Dennett, ar…Read more
  •  50
    Human Beings (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 1991.
    What is the importance of the notion 'human being'? The contributors to this collection have radically different approaches, some accepting and others denying its validity for a proper understanding of what a person is and for our ethical thought about each other. Contributors on both sides of the divide eloquently defend their views in ways that stand in sharp contrast to some current work in moral philosophy and philosophy of mind. Epistemological and theological issues are also raised in the …Read more
  •  51
    Capital Punishment and Realism
    Philosophy 66 (256). 1991.
    In its treatment of capital punishment Amnesty International gives a central place to the suffering of the prisoner. Two quite distinct forms of suffering are relevant here. There is the psychological anguish of the person awaiting execution; and there is the physical suffering which may be involved in the execution itself. It is suggested that if we reflect clearly on this suffering we will conclude that the death penalty involves cruelty of a kind which makes it quite unacceptable. It is to be…Read more
  •  6
    Booknotes
    Philosophy 64 (n/a): 275. 1989.
  •  57
    The Supernatural
    Religious Studies 28 (3). 1992.
    The final chapter of Peter Winch's book on Simone Weil discusses Weil's idea of supernatural virtue. Weil uses this language in connection with certain exceptional actions: actions of a kind which are for most of us, most of the time, simply impossible. She is particularly struck by cases in which someone refrains from exercising a power which they have over another: in which, for example, someone refrains from killing or enslaving an enemy who has grievously harmed him and who is now at his mer…Read more
  •  35
  •  6
    No Title available: New Books (review)
    Philosophy 67 (260): 262-264. 1992.
  •  14
    Introduction
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 29 1-9. 1991.
  •  16
    Reason and Persons
    Philosophical Investigations 10 (1): 54-72. 1987.
  •  17
    Freedom and Science
    Cogito 4 (2): 96-100. 1990.
  •  47
    Trust in Conversation
    Nordic Wittgenstein Review 3 (1): 47-68. 2014.
    We may think of the notion of “trust” primarily in epistemological terms or, alternatively, primarily in ethical terms. These different ways of thinking of trust are linked with different ways of picturing language, and my relation to the words of another. While an analogy with an individual continuing an arithmetical series has had a central place in discussions of language originating from Wittgenstein, Rush Rhees suggests that conversation provides a better model for thinking about language. …Read more
  •  15
    Memories, traces and the significance of the past
    In Christoph Hoerl & Teresa McCormark (eds.), Time and Memory, Oxford University Press. 2001.
  • Human Beings
    Philosophy 67 (262): 569-570. 1992.
  •  14
    Empiricism and the Theory of Meaning
    Philosophical Investigations 8 (1): 17-50. 1985.
  •  2
    Timely Topics
    Philosophical Books 37 (4): 268-269. 1996.
  •  31
    Tense and emotion
    In Robin Le Poidevin (ed.), Questions of Time and Tense, Oxford University Press. pp. 77--91. 1998.
  •  24
    In the Beginning Was the Deed
    Philosophical Investigations 36 (4): 303-319. 2013.
    Winch's readings of Wittgenstein and Weil call for a significant rethinking of the relation between “metaphysics” and “ethics.” But there are confusions, perhaps to be found in all three of these writers, that we may slip into here. These are linked with the tendency to see idealist tendencies in Wittgenstein, and with his remark that giving grounds comes to an end, not in a kind of seeing on our part, but in our acting. The sense that we think we see in this suggestion is dependent on a distort…Read more
  •  9
    This book differs from others by rejecting the dualist approach associated in particular with Descartes. It also casts serious doubt on the forms of materialism that now dominate English language philosophy. Drawing in particular on the work of Wittgenstein, a central place is given to the importance of the notion of a human being in our thought about ourselves and others.
  •  41
    The Non-Reality of Free Will.Freedom Within Reason
    with Richard Double and Susan Wolf
    Philosophical Quarterly 42 (168): 383. 1992.
  •  8
    Notebook
    Philosophy 64 (n/a): 282. 1989.