•  102
    Corporate responsibility requires a conception of collective agency on which collective agents are able to form moral judgments and act on them. In spite of claims to the contrary, existing accounts of collective agency fall short of this kind of corporate autonomy, as they fail to explain how collective agents might be responsive to moral reasons. I discuss how a recently proposed conception of shared valuing can be used for developing a solution to this problem. Although the resulting concepti…Read more
  •  138
    Corporate responsibility and judgment aggregation
    Economics and Philosophy 25 (2): 161-177. 2009.
    Paradoxical results concerning judgment aggregation have recently been invoked to defend the thesis that a corporate agent can be morally responsible for a decision without any of its individual members bearing such responsibility. I contend that the arguments offered for this irreducibility thesis are inconclusive. They do not pay enough attention to how we evaluate individual moral responsibility, in particular not to the role that a flawed assessment of the normative reasons that bear on the …Read more
  •  83
    Acceptance-dependence: A social kind of response-dependence
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 87 (4). 2006.
    Neither Johnston's nor Wright's account of response-dependence offers a complete picture of response-dependence, as they do not apply to all concepts that are intrinsically related to our mental responses. In order to (begin to) remedy this situation, a new conception of response-dependence is introduced that I call "acceptance-dependence". This account applies to concepts such as goal, constitutional, and money, the first two of which have mistakenly been taken to be response-dependent in anoth…Read more
  •  253
    The location problem in social ontology
    Synthese 190 (3): 413-437. 2013.
    Mental, mathematical, and moral facts are difficult to accommodate within an overall worldview due to the peculiar kinds of properties inherent to them. In this paper I argue that a significant class of social entities also presents us with an ontological puzzle that has thus far not been addressed satisfactorily. This puzzle relates to the location of certain social entities. Where, for instance, are organizations located? Where their members are, or where their designated offices are? Organiza…Read more
  • Review of Russell Hardin’s How do you know?: the economics of ordinary knowledge (review)
    Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 3 (1): 93-97. 2010.
  •  103
    People sometimes make moral judgments on the basis of brief emotional episodes. I follow the widely established practice of referring to such affective responses as intuitions (Haidt 2001, 2012; Bedke 2012, Copp 2012). Recently, a number of moral psychologists have argued that moral judgments are never more than emotion- or intuition-based pronouncements on what is right or wrong (Haidt 2001, Nichols 2004, Prinz 2007). A wide variety of empirical findings seem to support this claim. For example,…Read more
  • Emoties en intenties in de experimentele ethiek
    Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 102 (1): 2-13. 2010.
  •  195
    Collective Acceptance and the Is-Ought Argument
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16 (3): 465-480. 2013.
    According to John Searle’s well-known Is-Ought Argument, it is possible to derive an ought-statement from is-statements only. This argument concerns obligations involved in institutions such as promising, and it relies on the idea that institutions can be conceptualized in terms of constitutive rules. In this paper, I argue that the structure of this argument has never been fully appreciated. Starting from my status account of constitutive rules, I reconstruct the argument and establish that it …Read more
  •  86
    In the literature on social ontology, two perspectives on collective agency have been developed. The first is the internal perspective, the second the external one. The internal perspective takes the point of view of the members as its point of departure and appeals, inter alia, to the joint intentions they form. The idea is that collective agents perform joint actions such as dancing the tango, organizing prayer meetings, or performing symphonies. Such actions are generated by joint intentions,…Read more
  •  453
    Beyond the Big Four and the Big Five
    In Gerhard Preyer, Frank Hindriks & Sara Rachel Chant (eds.), From Individual to Collective Intentionality: New Essays, Oxford University Press. pp. 1-9. 2014.
  •  138
    The freedom of collective agents
    Journal of Political Philosophy 16 (2). 2007.
    Corporate freedom is the freedom of a collective agent to perform a joint action. According to a reductive account, a collective or corporate agent is free exactly if the individuals who constitute the corporate agent are free. It is argued that individual freedoms are neither necessary nor sufficient for corporate freedom. The alternative account proposed here focuses on the performance of the joint action by the corporate agent itself. Subsequently, the analysis is applied to Cohen’s (1983) an…Read more
  • Opzet en morele veranbvoordelijkheid in de experimentele filosofie
    Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 101 (1): 49-55. 2009.
  •  94
    How Does Reasoning Contribute to Moral Judgment? Dumbfounding and Disengagement
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (2): 237-250. 2015.
    Recent experiments in moral psychology have been taken to imply that moral reasoning only serves to reaffirm prior moral intuitions. More specifically, Jonathan Haidt concludes from his moral dumbfounding experiments, in which people condemn other people’s behavior, that moral reasoning is biased and ineffective, as it rarely makes people change their mind. I present complementary evidence pertaining to self-directed reasoning about what to do. More specifically, Albert Bandura’s experiments con…Read more
  •  332
    Constitutive Rules, Language, and Ontology
    Erkenntnis 71 (2): 253-275. 2009.
    It is a commonplace within philosophy that the ontology of institutions can be captured in terms of constitutive rules. What exactly such rules are, however, is not well understood. They are usually contrasted to regulative rules: constitutive rules (such as the rules of chess) make institutional actions possible, whereas regulative rules (such as the rules of etiquette) pertain to actions that can be performed independently of such rules. Some, however, maintain that the distinction between reg…Read more
  •  123
    A modest solution to the problem of rule-following
    Philosophical Studies 121 (1): 65-98. 2004.
    A modest solution to the problem(s) of rule-following is defended against Kripkensteinian scepticism about meaning. Even though parts of it generalise to other concepts, the theory as a whole applies to response-dependent concepts only. It is argued that the finiteness problem is not nearly as pressing for such concepts as it may be for some other kinds of concepts. Furthermore, the modest theory uses a notion of justification as sensitivity to countervailing conditions in order to solve the jus…Read more
  • The Metaphysics of Value (review)
    Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 4. 2005.
  •  265
    Restructuring Searle’s Making the Social World
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 43 (3): 373-389. 2013.
    Institutions are normative social structures that are collectively accepted. In his book Making the Social World, John R. Searle maintains that these social structures are created and maintained by Status Function Declarations. The article’s author criticizes this claim and argues, first, that Searle overestimates the role that language plays in relation to institutions and, second, that Searle’s notion of a Status Function Declaration confuses more than it enlightens. The distinction is exposed…Read more