•  152
    The Ontology of Mind: Events, States and Processes (review)
    Philosophical Review 108 (3): 418. 1999.
    The aim of this book is to argue that issues in metaphysics—in particular issues about the nature of states and causation—will have a significant impact in philosophy of mind. As Steward puts it: “the category of state has been so grossly misunderstood that some theories of mind which are supposed to encompass entities traditionally regarded as falling under the category, e.g., beliefs and desires, cannot so much as be sensibly formulated, once we are clearer about the nature of states”. Accordi…Read more
  •  16
    THOMSON, Judith Jarvis (1929– ) Judith Jarvis Thomson received her BA from Barnard College in 1950, her MA from Cambridge University in 1956, and a Ph.D. from Columbia University in 1959. Her first teaching position was at Barnard where she was a lecturer from 1955–9, an instructor from 1959–60, and then Assistant Professor from 1960–2. In 1963, she moved to Boston, first as an Assistant Professor at Boston University (1963–4), and then to the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, where she has…Read more
  •  2
    Shoemaker, S.-The First Person Perspective and Other Essays (review)
    Philosophical Books 39 105-108. 1998.
    This is a review essay of Sydney Shoemaker's The First-person Perspective and Other Essays
  •  473
    A neuron doctrine in the philosophy of neuroscience
    with Ian Gold
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (5): 809-830. 1999.
    It is widely held that a successful theory of the mind will be neuroscientific. In this paper we ask, first, what this claim means, and, secondly, whether it is true. In answer to the first question, we argue that the claim is ambiguous between two views--one plausible but unsubstantive, and one substantive but highly controversial. In answer to the second question, we argue that neither the evidence from neuroscience itself nor from other scientific and philosophical considerations supports the…Read more
  •  82
    Interpreting neuroscience and explaining the mind
    with Ian Gold
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (5): 856-866. 1999.
    Although a wide variety of questions were raised about different aspects of the target article, most of them fall into one of five categories each of which deals with a general question. These questions are Is the radical neuron doctrine really radical? Is the trivial neuron doctrine really trivial? Were we sufficiently critical of the radical neuron doctrine? Is there a distinction to be drawn at all between the two doctrines? and How does our argument bear on related issues in the ontology of …Read more
  •  70
    Qualitative Inaccuracy and Unconceived Alternatives
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 86 (3): 745-752. 2013.
    Pereboom (2011) is an extremely rich investigation of some of the central questions in contemporary philosophy of mind. In the foreground are the usual suspects from the current scene, but Kant and Russell loom in the background, and footnotes elaborate connections to people as apparently remote from the normal run of things as Dilthey and Derrida. With so much covered one is inevitably forced to focus on some things, setting aside others. Here I will concentrate on two ideas contained in the fi…Read more
  •  497
    Physicalism
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2015.
    Physicalism is the thesis that everything is physical, or as contemporary philosophers sometimes put it, that everything supervenes on, or is necessitated by, the physical. The thesis is usually intended as a metaphysical thesis, parallel to the thesis attributed to the ancient Greek philosopher Thales, that everything is water, or the idealism of the 18th Century philosopher Berkeley, that everything is mental. The general idea is that the nature of the actual world (i.e. the universe and every…Read more
  •  153
    What what it's like isn't like
    Analysis 56 (4): 281-83. 1996.
  •  169
    Ignorance and Imagination advances a novel way to resolve the central philosophical problem about the mind: how it is that consciousness or experience fits into a larger naturalistic picture of the world. The correct response to the problem, Stoljar argues, is not to posit a realm of experience distinct from the physical, nor to deny the reality of phenomenal experience, nor even to rethink our understanding of consciousness and the language we use to talk about it. Instead, we should view the p…Read more
  • The Content of Physicalism
    Dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology. 1995.
    Many philosophers of mind are concerned to defend the thesis called physicalism ; many others are concerned to refute it. Nevertheless, there is no generally agreed on idea of what physicalism is, and why it should matter whether the mental is physical. My thesis consists of four essays whose concern is with what physicalism is in its most plausible version, and what the importance of the thesis might be for the philosophy of mind. ;I begin with the question of whether it is possible to hold phy…Read more
  •  97
    Response to Alter and Bennett
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79 (3): 775-784. 2009.
    The paper responds to criticisms of *Ignorance and Imagination* offered by Torin Alter and Karen Bennett
  •  300
    Introspection and Consciousness (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2012.
    The topic of introspection stands at the interface between questions in epistemology about the nature of self-knowledge and questions in the philosophy of mind about the nature of consciousness. What is the nature of introspection such that it provides us with a distinctive way of knowing about our own conscious mental states? And what is the nature of consciousness such that we can know about our own conscious mental states by introspection? How should we understand the relationship between con…Read more
  •  103
    Nominalism and intentionality
    Noûs 30 (2): 221-241. 1996.
  •  301
    This paper defends a novel view of ‘what it is like’-sentences, according to which they attribute certain sorts of relations—I call them ‘affective relations’—that hold between events and individuals. The paper argues in detail for the superiority of this proposal over other views that are prevalent in the literature. The paper further argues that the proposal makes better sense than the alternatives of the widespread use of Nagel’s definition of conscious states and that it also shows the mista…Read more
  •  190
    The argument from revelation
    In Robert Nola & David Braddon Mitchell (eds.), Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism, Mit Press. 2009.
    1. Introduction The story of Canberra, the capital of Australia, is roughly as follows. In 1901, when what is called
  •  103
    Consciousness
    In Jessica Pfeifer & Sohartra Sarkar (eds.), The Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia, . pp. 158-163. 2005.
    Consciousness is extremely familiar yet it is at the limits—beyond the limits, some would say—of what one can sensibly talk about or explain. Perhaps this is the reason its study has drawn contributions from many fields including psychology, neuroscience, philosophy, anthropology, cultural and literary theory, artificial intelligence, physics, and others. The focus of this entry is on: the varieties of consciousness, different problems that have been raised about these varieties, and prospects f…Read more
  •  57
  •  31
    Crimmins, Gonzales and Moore
    with Alan Hájek
    Analysis 61 (3): 208-213. 2001.