• Action and Interpretation
    with P. Pettit
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (4): 396-401. 1980.
    Whether the interpretations made by social scientists of the thoughts, utterances and actions of other people, including those from an alien culture or a different period in history, are objectively correct, whether the forms of explanation they employ conform to those of the natural sciences, and whether values have a role in arriving at the theory that delivers the interpretations, are the main questions addressed by the contributors to this volume. Of particular importance in the discussion o…Read more
  • Evans, G., "Collected Papers" (review)
    Mind 96 (n/a): 280. 1987.
  •  1
    Books Received (review)
    Philosophy 53 (n/a): 427. 1978.
  •  3
    Notebook
    Philosophy 53 (n/a): 431. 1978.
    //static.cambridge.org/content/id/urn%3Acambridge.org%3Aid%3Aarticle%3AS0031819100022609/resource/name/firstPage-S0031819100022609a.jpg.
  •  7
    Galen Strawson, "Freedom and Belief" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 38 (53): 533. 1988.
  • Logical constructions and a priori knowledge
    Semiotica 99 (3-4): 401-420. 1994.
  • Comments on Peacocke
    Philosophical Books 42 (2): 101-105. 2001.
  •  1
    Gilbert Harman, "Change in View" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 39 (55): 242. 1989.
  •  1
    Unbestimmtheit und Interpretation
    In Philip Pettit & Christopher Hookway (eds.), Handlung Und Interpretation: Studien Zur Philosophie der Sozialwissenschaften, De Gruyter. pp. 27-57. 1982.
  • Peirce
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 22 (3): 327-338. 1986.
  •  6
    Review Article: Ethics and the Pragmatist Enlightenment
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 3 (2): 231-236. 2006.
  •  31
  • No Title available: Reviews
    Philosophy 89 (1): 180-184. 2014.
  •  9
    Reference, causation, and reality
    Semiotica 69 (3/4). 1988.
  •  33
    The Presidential Address: Questions of Context
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96 (1). 1996.
    Christopher Hookway; I *—The Presidential Address: Questions of Context, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 96, Issue 1, 1 June 1996, Pages 1–16, h.
  •  69
    Naturalized epistemology and epistemic evaluation
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 37 (4). 1994.
    The paper explores Quine's ?naturalized epistemology?, investigating whether its adoption would prevent the description or vindication of normative standards standardly employed in regulating beliefs and inquiries. Quine's defence of naturalized epistemology rejects traditional epistemological questions rather than using psychology to answer them. Although one could persuade those sensitive to the force of traditional epistemological problems only by employing the kind of argument whose philosop…Read more
  •  238
    Questions, epistemology, and inquiries
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 77 (1): 1-21. 2008.
    Questions are relevant to epistemology because they formulate cognitive goals, they are used to elicit information, they are used in Socratic reflection and knowledge sentences often have indirect question complements. The paper explores what capacities we must possess if we are to understand questions and identify and evaluate potential answers to them. The later sections explore different ways in which these matters depend upon pragmatic and other contextual considerations.
  •  44
    When deduction leads to belief
    Ratio 8 (1): 24-41. 1995.
    The paper questions the common assumption that rational individuals believe all propositions which they know to be logical consequences of their other beliefs: although we must acknowledge the truth of a proposition which is a deductive consequence of our beliefs, we may not genuinely believe it. This conclusion is defended by arguing that some familiar counterexamples to the claim that knowledge is justified true belief fail because they involve propositions which are not really believed. Belie…Read more
  •  36
    Design and Chance: The Evolution of Peirce's Evolutionary Cosmology
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 33 (1). 1997.
  •  3
    Thought and Reference
    Philosophical Books 30 (2): 97-100. 1989.
  • Michael Cabot Haley, "The Semeiosis of Poetic Metaphor" (review)
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 26 (1): 156. 1990.
  • Nature of Author: Editorial
    Philosophy 66 (255): 1-2. 1991.
  •  75
    Robert Brandom's latest book, the product of his John Locke lectures in Oxford in 2006, is a return to the philosophy of language and is easily read as a continuation and development of the views defended in Making it Explicit . The text of the lectures is presented much as they were delivered, but it contains an ‘Afterword’ of more than 30 pages which responds to questions raised when he gave the lectures, and also when they were subsequently delivered in Prague the following year. The publishe…Read more
  •  35
    How to be a Virtue Epistemologist
    In Linda Zagzebski & Michael DePaul (eds.), Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives From Ethics and Epistemology, Oxford University Press. pp. 183--202. 2003.
    This chapter points out that standard versions of virtue epistemology accept and are motivated by the same central problems in epistemology — such as analyzing the concepts of knowledge and justification, and addressing skeptical challenges — which motivate contemporary epistemology. The only significant difference is that virtue epistemology claims that the concepts of knowledge and justification must be analyzed in terms of virtues. What motivates virtue ethicists, however, is not what is moti…Read more