•  45
    Back to the drawing board
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (4): 509-518. 2005.
    Within ontology new theories are extremely rare. Hacking bravely claims to have one: "historical ontology" or "dynamic nominalism." Regrettably, he uses "nominalism" idiosyncratically, without explaining it or its qualifier. He does say what historical ontology is: it is "the presentation of the history of ontology in context." This idea is laudable, as it invites presenting idealism as once attractive but no longer so (due to changes in perception theory, for example). But this idea is a propos…Read more
  •  44
    Analogies as generalizations
    Philosophy of Science 31 (4): 351-356. 1964.
    Analogies have been traditionally recognized as a proper part of inductive procedures, akin to generalizations. Seldom, however, have they been presented as superior to generalizations, in the attainability of a higher degree of certitude for their conclusions or in other respects. Though Bacon definitely preferred analogy to generalization, the tradition seems to me to go the other way—until the recent publication of works by Mary B. Hesse and, perhaps, R. Harré.
  •  39
    Popper and His Popular Critics: Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos: Appendix
    Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 59 (4): 181-188. 2022.
    Popper’s popular critics – Kuhn, Feyerabend, and Lakatos – replace his older, Wittgenstein-style critics, now defunct. His new critics played with the idea of criticism as beneficial, in vain search of variants of these that could better appeal to the public. Some of their criticism of Popper is valid but marginal for the dispute about rationality. He was Fallibilist; they hedged about it. He viewed learning from experience as learning from error; they were unclear about it. His view resembles F…Read more
  •  37
    Global Responsibility
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 7 (2): 217-221. 1990.
    ABSTRACT Concern with global responsibility for survival as such invites the creation of a specific international organization. The new body should adjudicate as to which disputes are open (such as, for example, concerning the advisability of building nuclear plants) and which are not (for example, white supremacy); most significantly, the new body should carefully guard its credibility by sticking to veracity, by avoiding deceit even in extreme situations. In particular it behoves us all to con…Read more
  •  36
    Both a Popper biography and an autobiography, Agassi's "A Philosopher's Apprentice" tells the riveting story of his intellectual formation in 1950s London, a young brilliant philosopher struggling with an intellectual giant - father, mentor, and rival, all at the same time. His subsequent rebellion and declaration of independence leads to a painful break, never to be completely healed. No other writer has Agassi's psychological insight into Popper, and no other book captures like this one the in…Read more
  •  34
    Bye-bye, Weber
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 21 (1): 102-109. 1991.
    Peter Lassman and Irving Velody, with Herminio Martins, eds., Max Weber's " Science as a Vocation ." Unwin Hyman, London, 1989. Pp. 213, US$49.95.
  •  33
    Newell's list
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (5): 601-602. 2003.
    Newell wanted a theory of cognition to abide by some explicit criteria, here called the Newell Test. The test differs from the Turing Test because it is explicit. The Newell Test will include the Turing Test if its characterization of cognition is complete. It is not. Its use here is open-ended: A system that does not pass it well invites improvement.
  •  33
    The Grounds of Reason
    with I. C. Jarvie and Tom Settle
    Philosophy 46 (175). 1971.
  •  32
    An Unpublished Paper of the Young Faraday
    with Michael Faraday
    Isis 52 (1): 87-90. 1961.
  •  32
    Changing our background-knowledge (review)
    Synthese 19 (3-4): 453-464. 1969.
  •  31
  •  28
    False prophecy versus true Quest a modest challenge to contemporary relativists
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 22 (3): 285-312. 1992.
    A good theory of rationality should accommodate debates over first principles, such as those of rationality. The modest challenge made in this article is that relativists try to explain the (intellectual) value of some debates about first principles (absolute presuppositions, basic assumptions, intellectual frameworks, intellectual commitments, and paradigms). Relativists claim to justify moving with relative ease from one framework to another, translating chunks of one into the other; this tech…Read more
  •  26
    Jacob Katz, Tradition and Crisis: Jewish Society at the End of the Middle Ages , in Hebrew, Jerusalem, .1953, pp. 310. English translation, 1961.
  •  26
    Tristram Shandy, Pierre Menard, and all that (review)
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 14 (n/a): 152. 1971.
  •  25
    Summary and conclusions
    with David Martel Johnson
    As a new field, cognitivism began with the total rejection of the old, traditional views of language acquisition and of learning ─ individual and collective alike. Chomsky was one of the pioneers in this respect, yet he clouds issues by excessive claims for his originality and by not allowing the beginner in the art of the acquisition of language the use of learning by making hypotheses and testing them, though he acknowledges that researchers, himself included, do use this method. The most impo…Read more
  •  25
    An inductivist version of critical rationalism
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 24 (4): 458-465. 1994.
  •  25
    Bunge Nevertheless
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 43 (4): 542-562. 2013.
    Mario Bunge offers here a political philosophy and a view of current politics as judged by his vision of an integrated democracy that is thoroughly green, quasi-communalist, participatory, and quasi-socialist; all enterprises there belong to their workers. He tempers his egalitarianism with some meritocracy. His vision is impracticable but deserves examination
  •  24
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Ahead of Print.
  •  24
    A Touch of Malice
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32 (1): 107-119. 2002.
  •  24
  •  23
    Self- Deception in General "A Liberal Decalogue" suggests (Russell, 1967, pp. 60-61) not to envy people who live in a fool's paradise: It is a place only for fools. This saying invites detailed commentary. A fool's paradise is not a place, but a state o f mind; it is a system of opinions, of assessments of situations, that calms one down, that reassures one into the opinion that all is well, even when all is far from well. Fools may be ignorant of the severity of their situations, perhaps becaus…Read more
  •  23
    A B s T r a C t
    with Shlomo Biderman and Ben-Ami Scharfstein
    The traditional hermeneutic ruling not to use reports and legends for questioning edicts and rules signifies the tacit recognition, contrary to explicit statement, of the part of the Rabbinical leadership, of the inevitability of change in diverse aspects if Jewish life. This may invite criticism of the conduct of the ancient leadership, which, as always, is questionable and useless. Rather, an open discussion should be instituted on the proposal to make future changes openly, not surreptitiousl…Read more
  •  22
    The Politics of Science
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 3 (1): 35-48. 1986.
    ABSTRACT The myth that there is no politics of science is dangerous as it prevents the important and urgently needed institution of some democratic control of the existing system of politics within the commonwealth of learning. Feyerabend's attack on science makes sense only when understood in this way.
  •  22
    Summary and conclusions As a new field, cognitivism began with the total rejection of the old, traditional views of language acquisition and of learning -- individual and collective alike. Chomsky was one of the pioneers in this respect, yet he clouds issues by excessive claim s for his originality and by not allowing the beginner in the art of the acquisition of language the use of learning by making hypotheses and testing them, though he acknowledges that researchers, himself included, do use …Read more
  •  21
    Contemporary European Philosophy, After Half-a-Century (review)
    Polish Journal of Philosophy 5 (1): 139-148. 2011.
  •  20
    A Critical Rationalist Aesthetics (edited book)
    with Ian Charles Jarvie
    Rodopi. 2008.
    This book is a first attempt to cover the whole area of aesthetics from the point of view of critical rationalism. It takes up and expands upon the more narrowly focused work of E. H. Gombrich, Sheldon Richmond, and Raphael Sassower and Louis Ciccotello. The authors integrate the arts into the scientific world view and acknowledge that there is an aesthetic aspect to anything whatsoever. They pay close attention to the social situatedness of the arts. Their aesthetics treats art as emerging from…Read more