•  280
    Political liberty: Who needs it?
    Social Philosophy and Policy 29 (1): 1-27. 2012.
    Research Articles Jason Brennan, Social Philosophy and Policy, FirstView Article
  •  37
    Equality, Community, and Diversity in Cohen’s Socialist Ideal
    Analyse & Kritik 37 (1-2): 113-130. 2015.
    The ‘community principle’ is crucial to G. A. Cohen’s argument for socialism, because it is the best independent argument he has adduced for his strongly egalitarian conclusions. Cohen argues that even small differences in wealth ought to be prohibited because they bring us out of community with one another. In this paper, I show that his underlying premises lead to some repugnant conclusions, and thus should be rejected. If Cohen is right that even small differences in wealth can upset communit…Read more
  •  19
    Why Liberal States Must Accommodate Tax Resistors
    Public Affairs Quarterly. forthcoming.
    Liberal states ought to accommodate conscientious tax resistance for the same reasons they should accommodate conscientious objection to fighting in war. Conscientious objection to fighting is nothing special.
  •  248
    The Ethics of Voting
    Princeton Univ Pr. 2011.
    In this provocative book, Jason Brennan challenges our fundamental assumptions about voting, revealing why it is not a duty for most citizens--in fact, he ...
  •  130
    Modesty without Illusion
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (1): 111-128. 2007.
    The common image of the fully virtuous person is of someone with perfect self‐command and self‐perception, who always makes correct evaluations. However, modesty appears to be a real virtue, and it seems contradictory for someone to believe that she is modest. Accordingly, traditional defenders of phronesis (the view that virtue involves practical wisdom) deny that modesty is a virtue, while defenders of modesty such as Julia Driver deny that phronesis is required for virtue. I offer a new theor…Read more
  •  276
    Classical Liberalism
    with John Tomasi
    In David Estlund (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy, Oxford University Press, Usa. pp. 115. 2012.
  •  1205
    For-Profit Business as Civic Virtue
    Journal of Business Ethics 106 (3): 313-324. 2012.
    According to the commonsense view of civic virtue, the places to exercise civic virtue are largely restricted to politics. In this article, I argue for a more expansive view of civic virtue, and argue that one can exercise civic virtue equally well through working for or running a for-profit business. I argue that this conclusion follows from four relatively uncontroversial premises: (1) the consensus definition of “civic virtue”, (2) the standard, most popular theory of virtuous activity, (3) a…Read more
  •  201
    When may we kill government agents? In defense of moral parity
    Social Philosophy and Policy 32 (2): 40-61. 2016.
    :This essay argues for what may be called the parity thesis: Whenever it would be morally permissible to kill a civilian in self-defense or in defense of others against that civilian's unjust acts, it would also be permissible to kill government officials, including police officers, prison officers, generals, lawmakers, and even chief executives. I argue that in realistic circumstances, violent resistance to state injustice is permissible, even and perhaps especially in reasonably just democrati…Read more
  •  413
    Polluting the Polls: When Citizens Should Not Vote
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87 (4): 535-549. 2009.
    Just because one has the right to vote does not mean just any vote is right. Citizens should not vote badly. This duty to avoid voting badly is grounded in a general duty not to engage in collectively harmful activities when the personal cost of restraint is low. Good governance is a public good. Bad governance is a public bad. We should not be contributing to public bads when the benefit to ourselves is low. Many democratic theorists agree that we shouldn’t vote badly, but that’s because t…Read more
  •  50
    Estimating the Cost of Justice for Adjuncts: A Case Study in University Business Ethics
    with Phillip Magness
    Journal of Business Ethics 148 (1): 155-168. 2018.
    American universities rely upon a large workforce of adjunct faculty—contract workers who receive low pay, no benefits, and no job security. Many news sources, magazines, and activists claim that adjuncts are exploited and should receive better pay and treatment. This paper never affirms nor denies that adjuncts are exploited. Instead, we show that any attempt to provide a significantly better deal faces unpleasant constraints and trade-offs. “Adjunct justice” would cost universities somewhere b…Read more
  •  147
    Beyond the Bottom Line: The Theoretical Goals of Moral Theorizing
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 28 (2): 277-296. 2008.
    Moral theory is no substitute for virtue, but virtue is no substitute for moral theory. Many critics of moral theory, with Richard Posner being one prominent recent example, complain that moral theory is too abstract, that it cannot generally be used to derive particular rights and wrongs, and that it does not improve people's characters. Posner complains that it is thus of no use to legal theorists. This article defends moral theory, and to some degree, philosophical inquiry in general, against…Read more