•  37
    In defence of logical nominalism: Reply to leftow1: Richard Swinburne
    Religious Studies 46 (3): 311-330. 2010.
    This paper defends logical nominalism, the thesis that logically necessary truth belongs primarily to sentences and depends solely on the conventions of human language. A sentence is logically necessary iff its negation entails a contradiction. A sentence is a posteriori metaphysically necessary iff it reduces to a logical necessity when we substitute for rigid designators of objects or properties canonical descriptions of the essential properties of those objects or properties. The truth-condit…Read more
  •  47
    Authority of scripture, tradition, and the church
    In Thomas P. Flint & Michael Rea (eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophical theology, Oxford University Press. 2008.
    Christianity, Islam, and Judaism all claim that God has given humans a revelation. Divine revelation may be either of God, or by God of propositional truth. Traditionally Christianity has claimed that the Christian revelation has involved both of these. God revealed himself in his acts in history; for example in the miracles by which he preserved the people of ancient Israel, and above all by becoming incarnate as Jesus Christ, who was crucified and rose from the dead. And God also revealed to u…Read more
  •  1
    The Dark Tide
    Oxford University Press UK. 1993.
    The author investigates what it means, and whether it is coherent, to say that there is a God, concluding that, despite philosophical objections, the claims which religious believers make about God are generally coherent. Sometimes the words by which this is expressed are used in a stretched sense, but theologians acknowledge the fact.
  •  170
    Providence and the Problem of Evil
    Oxford University Press UK. 1998.
    Richard Swinburne offers an answer to one of the most difficult problems of religious belief: why does a loving God allow humans to suffer so much? It is the final instalment of Swinburne's acclaimed four-volume philosophical examination of Christian doctrine
  •  152
    Dualism Intact
    Faith and Philosophy 13 (1): 68-77. 1996.
    I have argued in many places that a carefully articulated version of Descartes’ argument to show that he is essentially an immaterial soul is sound. It is conceivable that I who am currently conscious continue to exist without my body, and that can only be if there is currently a non-bodily part of me which alone is essential for me. Recent counter-arguments of Alston and Smythe, Moser and van der Nat, Zimmerman, and Shoemaker are rejected.
  •  198
    Response to Reviewers
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 6 (2): 51--63. 2014.
  •  12
    How God makes all the difference to morality
    Disputatio Philosophica 6 (1): 135-145. 2004.
  • Could God Become Man? IN The Philosophy in Christianity
    In , Cambridge University Press. 1989.
    Christian orthodoxy has maintained that in Jesus Christ God became man, i.e., acquired a human nature, while remaining God. Given two not unreasonable restrictions on the understanding of "man", that claim is perfectly coherent. But if the New Testament is correct in claiming that in some sense Christ was ignorant, weak, and temptable, we have to suppose that Christ has a divided mind; or, in traditional terminology, that the two natures did not totally interpenetrate.
  •  13
    Review: Response to Warrant (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2). 1995.
  •  47
    God as the Simplest Explanation of the Universe
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 68 3-24. 2011.
    I have argued over many years that theism provides a probably true explanation of the existence and most general features of the universe. A major reason for this, I have claimed, is that it is simpler than other explanations. The present paper seeks to amplify and defend this latter claim in the light of some recent challenges.
  •  30
    An Introduction to Confirmation Theory
    with Mark Pastin
    Philosophical Review 84 (1): 122. 1975.
  •  318
    The Beginning of the Universe and of Time
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26 (2). 1996.
    Given four modest verificationist theses, tying the meaning of talk about instants and periods to the events which (physically) could occur during, before or after them, the only content to the claim the Universe had a beginning (applicable equally to chaotic or orderly universes) is in terms of it being preceded by empty time. It follows that time cannot have a beginning. The Universe, however, could have a beginning--even if it has lasted for an infinite time.
  •  10
    No title available: Religious studies
    Religious Studies 16 (2): 239-242. 1980.
  • Book notices-the evolution of the soul
    History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 20 (1): 127. 1998.
  •  9
    The Rationality of Theism (edited book)
    Rodopi. 2000.
    This is a controversial collection of brand new papers by some outstanding philosophers and scholars. Its aim is to offer comprehensive theistic replies to the traditional arguments against the existence of God.
  •  132
    Reason and the Christian religion: essays in honour of Richard Swinburne (edited book)
    with Alan G. Padgett
    Oxford University Press. 1994.
    Richard Swinburne is one of the most distinguished philosophers of religion of our day. In this volume, many notable British and American philosophers unite to honor him and to discuss various topics to which he has contributed significantly. These include general topics in the philosophy of religion such as revelation, and faith and reason, and the specifically Christian doctrines of the Trinity, the Incarnation, and atonement. In the spirit of the movement which Swinburne spearheaded, the essa…Read more
  •  4
    Free To Do Evil
    The Philosophers' Magazine 5 49-51. 1999.
  •  2
    Theism
    Philosophical Books 27 (3): 191-192. 1986.
  •  69
    Necessary a Posteriori Truth
    American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (2). 1991.
    Two sentences express the same proposition if they are synonymous; they express the same statement if they attribute the same properties to the same objects at the same time (however objects and times are picked out). Neither propositions nor statements are necessary a posteriori. Suggested examples of the necessary a posteriori, such as "Hesperus is Phosphorus", or "water is H2O", only appear to be such because of a confusion between proposition and statement.
  •  150
    The Limits of Explanation
    Philosophy 27 (Supplement). 1990.
    Scientific explanation in terms of laws and initial conditions (or better, in terms of objects with powers and liabilities) is contrasted with personal explanation in terms of agents with powers and purposes. In each case the factors involved in explanation may themselves be explained, and infinite regress of explanation is logically possible. There can be no absolute explanation of phenomena, which is explanation in terms of the logically necessary; but there can be ultimate explanation which i…Read more
  • Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32 (3): 314-318. 1981.
  •  212
    Epistemic justification
    Oxford University Press. 2001.
    Richard Swinburne offers an original treatment of a question at the heart of epistemology: what makes a belief rational, or justified in holding? He maps the rival accounts of philosophers on epistemic justification ("internalist" and "externalist"), arguing that they are really accounts of different concepts. He distinguishes between synchronic justification (justification at a time) and diachronic justification (synchronic justification resulting from adequate investigation)--both internalist …Read more
  •  20
    Language and Time
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2): 486-489. 1996.
    Part I of Language and Time is a defence of the tensed theory of time, the view that assertions about events happening now or being past or future are irreducible to tenseless assertions about the dates at which events happen or about their occurrence before or after other events. It claims that tensed sentences are not translatable by tenseless sentences, nor do they have the same truth conditions as tenseless sentences. They are reducible in neither of these senses either to tenseless date sen…Read more
  • "Alvin Plantinga," edited by James E. Tomberlin and Peter van Inwagen (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (3): 511. 1987.