•  169
    The Coherence of Theism (revised edition)
    Oxford University Press. 1977.
    This book investigates what it means, and whether it is coherent, to say that there is a God.
  •  11
    Predictivism
    Linguistic and Philosophical Investigations 8 71-85. 2009.
  •  129
    Design defended: Swinburne Defending design
    Think 2 (6): 13-18. 2004.
    Richard Swinburne responds to criticisms of his arguments from design for the existence of God.
  •  6
    Why God allows evil
    In Steven M. Cahn (ed.), Exploring Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology, Oxford University Press Usa. 2000.
  •  52
    Reply to Richard Gale
    Religious Studies 36 (2): 221-225. 2000.
    I am most grateful to Richard Gale for the detailed attention which he has paid to my detailed arguments, and for the kind remarks between which he sandwiches his hard-hitting criticisms. The first of the latter is that I (211) between different theses, Ss, Sw, and W. I hope not, but I agree that I may not have made the relation between these sufficiently clear. I am certainly committed to, and sought to argue for, the strong version of the strong thesis
  • Gott und Zeit
    In Ch JäGer (ed.), Analytische Religionsphilosophie, Ferdinand Schã¶ningh. 1998.
  •  3
    Time and Eternity (review)
    Religious Studies 38 (3): 363-369. 2002.
  •  1
    No Title available: New Books (review)
    Philosophy 71 (277): 465-468. 1996.
  •  53
    Could God Become Man?
    Philosophy 25 (Supplement). 1989.
    Christian orthodoxy has maintained that in Jesus Christ God became man, i.e., acquired a human nature, while remaining God. Given two not unreasonable restrictions on the understanding of "man," that claim is perfectly coherent. But if the New Testament is correct in claiming that in some sense Christ was ignorant, weak, and temptable, we have to suppose that Christ had a divided mind; or, in traditional terminology, that the two natures did not totally interpenetrate.
  • The soul
    In Timothy O'Connor & David Robb (eds.), Philosophy of Mind: Contemporary Readings, Routledge. 2003.
  •  3
    Rational religious belief
    In Kevin Timpe (ed.), Arguing about religion, Routledge. pp. 40. 2009.
  •  12
    God and Time
    In Eleonore Stump (ed.), Reasoned Faith, Cornell University Press. pp. 204-222. 1993.
    Four principles about Time have the consequence that God must be everlasting, and not timeless. These are 1) events occur over periods of time, never at instants, 2) Time has a metric if and only if there is a unified system of laws of nature, 3) The past is the realm of the causally unaffectible, the future of the causally affectible, 4) Some truths can only be known at certain periods. Yet God is not Time’s prisoner’, for the unwelcome features of Time--the increase of unaffectible events, the…Read more
  •  13
    Richard Garner
    with Tensed Facts
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 68 (2). 1990.
  •  17
    Many Kinds of Rational Theistic Belief
    In G. Bruntrup & R. K. Tacelli (eds.), The Rationality of Theism, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 21--38. 1999.
    After a discussion of several concepts of explanation, in which the criterion of simplicity is emphasized and some interesting historical examples are used as illustration, this paper presents the cosmological and teleological arguments. The central claim is that the hypothesis of theism is more simple and elegant and so more rational than any of its alternatives.
  •  73
    Free To Do Evil
    The Philosophers' Magazine 5 (5): 49-51. 1999.
  •  63
    Second reply to grünbaum
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56 (4): 919-925. 2005.
    I give a detailed defence against Grunbaum’s 2004 attack on my Bayesian argument for the existence of God from various features of the universe (its conformity to simple laws, the laws being such as to lead to the evolution of humans, etc.). Theism postulates the simplest possible stopping point for explanation of the various features which I mention, and is such that it makes the accounts of those features more probable than they would be otherwise
  •  5
    Introduction to Bayes's Theorem
    In Bayes’s Theorem, Oxford University Press. 2002.
    This is an introduction to a collected volume. It distinguishes between evidential, statistical, and physical probability, and between objective and subjective understandings of evidential probability, in the use of Bayes’s theorem. If Bayes’s theorem is to be used to assess an objective evidential probability, a priori criteria--mainly the criterion of simplicity--are required to determine prior probability. The five main contributors to the volume discuss the use of Bayes’s theorem to assess t…Read more
  • O artigo discute a forma de um argumento em favor da ressurreição de Jesus do modo como o Cristianismo acredita que esta ocorreu, o qual, se bem-sucedido, seria um forte indício histórico da existência de Deus. O artigo sustenta que Deus teve boas razões para se encarnar por certos propósitos e que, se assim ele o fez, ele viveria um certo tipo de vida como um ser humano, que seria culminada por um supermilagre como sua ressurreição. Se encontrarmos um e apenas um ser humano em toda a história s…Read more
  •  95
    The Existence of God
    Oxford University Press UK. 1979.
    Richard Swinburne presents a substantially rewritten and updated edition of his most celebrated book. No other work has made a more powerful case for the probability of the existence of God. Swinburne gives a rigorous and penetrating analysis of the most important arguments for theism: the cosmological argument; arguments from the existence of laws of nature and the 'fine-tuning' of the universe; from the occurrence of consciousness and moral awareness; and from miracles and religious experience…Read more
  •  1
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (4): 401-404. 1980.
  •  7
    Evil does not show that there is no God
    In Brian Davies (ed.), Philosophy of Religion: A Guide and Anthology, Oxford University Press. pp. 599--613. 2000.
  •  6
    Review of Elliott Sober: Simplicity (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27 (4): 412-414. 1976.
  •  214
    Arguments from Design
    Think 1 (1). 2002.
    I distinguish between the argument to the existence of God from the operation of laws of nature and the argument from the laws being of such a kind as (together with the boundary conditions of the universe) to lead to the evolution of humans. There could not be a ’scientific’ explanation of these data, but there could be a ’personal’ explanation that they were caused by a person in virtue of his powers and purposes. The simplest and so most probably true explanation is that they were brought abo…Read more
  •  9
    The Christian Scheme of Salvation
    In Thomas V. Morris (ed.), Philosophy and the Christian Faith, Univ. of Notre Dame Press. pp. 13-30. 1988.
    FAILURE TO OBSERVE OBLIGATIONS PRODUCES OBJECTIVE GUILT; FAILURE TO OBSERVE BELIEVED OBLIGATIONS PRODUCES SUBJECTIVE GUILT. A GUILTY PERSON MUST MAKE ATONEMENT. ATONEMENT CONSISTS OF REPENTANCE, APOLOGY, REPARATION AND PENANCE. THE PROCESS OF UNDOING THE WRONG IS COMPLETED WHEN THE WRONGED PERSON FORGIVES. NO ONE CAN MAKE THE GUILTY ONE’S REPENTANCE AND APOLOGY FOR HIM, BUT ANOTHER CAN PROVIDE THE MEANS OF REPARATION AND PENANCE. WHEN HUMANS SIN AGAINST GOD THEY NEED TO APOLOGISE WITH REPENTANCE…Read more
  •  363
    Prior Probabilities in the Argument From Fine-Tuning
    Faith and Philosophy 22 (5): 641-653. 2005.
    Theism is a far simpler hypothesis, and so a priori more probably true, than naturalism, understood as the hypothesis that the existence of this law-governeduniverse has no explanation. Theism postulates only one entity (God) with very simple properties, whereas naturalism has to postulate either innumerableentities all having the same properties, or one very complicated entity with the power to produce the former. If theism is true, it is moderately probable that God would create humanoid being…Read more
  •  772
    What Kind of Necessary Being Could God Be?
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 4 (2): 1--18. 2012.
    A logically impossible sentence is one which entails a contradiction, a logically necessary sentence is one whose negation entails a contradiction, and a logically possible sentence is one which does not entail a contradiction. Metaphysically impossible, necessary and possible sentences are ones which become logically impossible, necessary, or possible by substituting what I call informative rigid designators for uninformative ones. It does seem very strongly that a negative existential sentence…Read more