•  29
    XIII*—Personal Identity
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 74 (1): 231-247. 1974.
    R. G. Swinburne; XIII*—Personal Identity, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 74, Issue 1, 1 June 1974, Pages 231–247, https://doi.org/10.1093/arist.
  • Book reviews (review)
    Mind 85 (337): 131-134. 1976.
  • Book reviews (review)
    Mind 86 (342): 301-303. 1977.
  • Book reviews (review)
    Mind 87 (3): 450-452. 1978.
  • Book reviews (review)
    Mind 90 (359): 468-470. 1981.
  • Book reviews (review)
    Mind 91 (361): 139-141. 1982.
  •  6
    Review of R. D. Rosenkrantz: Inference, Method and Decision (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (3): 301-304. 1978.
  •  33
    Faith and the Existence of God
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 24 121-143. 1988.
    Arguments move from premises to conclusions. The premises state things taken temporally for granted; if the argument works, the premises provide grounds for affirming the conclusion. A valid deductive argument is one in which the premises necessitate, that is, entail, the conclusion. What I shall call a ‘correct’ inductive argument is one in which the premises in some degree probabilify the conclusion, but do not necessitate it. More precisely, in what I shall call a correct P-inductive argument…Read more
  •  9
    No Title available: REVIEWS
    Religious Studies 13 (3): 355-357. 1977.
  •  70
    The Christian Wager: R. G. SWINBURNE
    Religious Studies 4 (2): 217-228. 1969.
    On what grounds will the rational man become a Christian? It is often assumed by many, especially non-Christians, that he will become a Christian if and only if he judges that the evidence available to him shows that it is more likely than not that the Christian theological system is true, that, in mathematical terms, on the evidence available to him, the probability of its truth is greater than half. It is the purpose of this paper to investigate whether or not this is a necessary and sufficien…Read more
  • HINCKFUSS, I. "The Existence of Space and Time" (review)
    Mind 86 (n/a): 301. 1977.
  • PLANTINGA, A. "The Nature of Necessity" (review)
    Mind 85 (n/a): 131. 1976.
  • NERLICH, G. "The Shape of Space" (review)
    Mind 87 (n/a): 450. 1978.
  • VESEY, G. "Personal Identity" (review)
    Mind 85 (n/a): 143. 1976.
  •  1
    Notebook
    Philosophy 62 (n/a): 550. 1987.
  •  8
    Editorial: Guest Editorial: Open Letter
    Philosophy 63 (n/a): 1. 1988.
  • HARRISON, ROSS "On What There Must Be" (review)
    Philosophy 50 (n/a): 118. 1975.
  •  5
    Books Received (review)
    Philosophy 62 (n/a): 547. 1987.
  • David Lewis
    In Daniel Kolak & R. Martin (eds.), Self and Identity: Contemporary Philosophical Issues, Macmillan. pp. 273. 1991.
  •  3
    Book Reviews (review)
    Mind 100 (399): 406-408. 1991.
  •  34
    New Studies in Philosophy of Religion.Death and Immortality.Religion and Secularisation.The Concept of Miracle.Morality and Religion (review)
    with Graham Slater, W. D. Hudson, D. Z. Phillips, Vernon Pratt, and W. W. Bartley Iii
    Philosophical Quarterly 22 (86): 89. 1972.
  •  29
    Selected Writings, 1909-1953
    with Hans Reichenbach, Maria Reichenbach, and Robert S. Cohen
    Philosophical Quarterly 30 (119): 152. 1980.
  •  33
    The Philosophy of Karl Popper
    with P. A. Schilpp
    Philosophical Quarterly 25 (101): 365. 1975.
  •  20
    Faith and the Existence of God: Arguments for the Existence of God
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 24 121-133. 1988.
    Arguments move from premises to conclusions. The premises state things taken temporally for granted; if the argument works, the premises provide grounds for affirming the conclusion. A valid deductive argument is one in which the premises necessitate, that is, entail, the conclusion. What I shall call a ‘correct’ inductive argument is one in which the premises in some degree probabilify the conclusion, but do not necessitate it. More precisely, in what I shall call a correct P-inductive argument…Read more
  •  29
    Original Sinfulness
    Neue Zeitschrift für Systematicsche Theologie Und Religionsphilosophie 27 (1): 235-250. 1985.
  •  130
    Omnipotence
    American Philosophical Quarterly 10 (3). 1973.
    CAN A COHERENT ACCOUNT BE PROVIDED OF WHAT IT IS FOR A BEING TO BE OMNIPOTENT, WHICH BRINGS OUT WHAT THEISTS HAVE WANTED TO SAY WHEN THEY CLAIM THAT GOD IS OMNIPOTENT? IT IS ARGUED THAT IT CAN. A BEING S IS SAID TO BE OMNIPOTENT AT A TIME T IF FOR ANY LOGICALLY CONTINGENT STATE OF AFFAIRS X AFTER T, SUCH THAT THE OCCURRENCE OF X AFTER T DOES NOT ENTAIL THAT S DID NOT BRING ABOUT X AT T, S IS ABLE AT T TO BRING ABOUT X. THIS ACCOUNT IS IMMUNE TO DIFFICULTIES SUCH AS THOSE OFFERED BY THE PARADOX O…Read more
  •  20