•  2
  •  167
    Providence and the Problem of Evil
    Oxford University Press UK. 1998.
    Richard Swinburne offers an answer to one of the most difficult problems of religious belief: why does a loving God allow humans to suffer so much? It is the final instalment of Swinburne's acclaimed four-volume philosophical examination of Christian doctrine
  •  150
    Dualism Intact
    Faith and Philosophy 13 (1): 68-77. 1996.
    I have argued in many places that a carefully articulated version of Descartes’ argument to show that he is essentially an immaterial soul is sound. It is conceivable that I who am currently conscious continue to exist without my body, and that can only be if there is currently a non-bodily part of me which alone is essential for me. Recent counter-arguments of Alston and Smythe, Moser and van der Nat, Zimmerman, and Shoemaker are rejected.
  • What Philosophers Think
    Continuum Press. 2003.
  •  188
    Response to Reviewers
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 6 (2): 51--63. 2014.
  •  12
    How God makes all the difference to morality
    Disputatio Philosophica 6 (1): 135-145. 2004.
  •  9
    No title available: Religious studies
    Religious Studies 16 (2): 239-242. 1980.
  • Could God Become Man? IN The Philosophy in Christianity
    In , Cambridge University Press. 1989.
    Christian orthodoxy has maintained that in Jesus Christ God became man, i.e., acquired a human nature, while remaining God. Given two not unreasonable restrictions on the understanding of "man", that claim is perfectly coherent. But if the New Testament is correct in claiming that in some sense Christ was ignorant, weak, and temptable, we have to suppose that Christ has a divided mind; or, in traditional terminology, that the two natures did not totally interpenetrate.
  •  6
    Why God allows evil
    In Steven M. Cahn (ed.), Exploring Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology, Oxford University Press Usa. 2000.
  •  13
    Review: Response to Warrant (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2). 1995.
  •  46
    God as the Simplest Explanation of the Universe
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 68 3-24. 2011.
    I have argued over many years that theism provides a probably true explanation of the existence and most general features of the universe. A major reason for this, I have claimed, is that it is simpler than other explanations. The present paper seeks to amplify and defend this latter claim in the light of some recent challenges.
  •  30
    An Introduction to Confirmation Theory
    with Mark Pastin
    Philosophical Review 84 (1): 122. 1975.
  •  169
    The Coherence of Theism (revised edition)
    Oxford University Press. 1977.
    This book investigates what it means, and whether it is coherent, to say that there is a God.
  •  69
    Necessary a Posteriori Truth
    American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (2). 1991.
    Two sentences express the same proposition if they are synonymous; they express the same statement if they attribute the same properties to the same objects at the same time (however objects and times are picked out). Neither propositions nor statements are necessary a posteriori. Suggested examples of the necessary a posteriori, such as "Hesperus is Phosphorus", or "water is H2O", only appear to be such because of a confusion between proposition and statement.
  • Book notices-the evolution of the soul
    History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 20 (1): 127. 1998.
  • The soul
    In Timothy O'Connor & David Robb (eds.), Philosophy of Mind: Contemporary Readings, Routledge. 2003.
  •  128
    Reason and the Christian religion: essays in honour of Richard Swinburne (edited book)
    with Alan G. Padgett
    Oxford University Press. 1994.
    Richard Swinburne is one of the most distinguished philosophers of religion of our day. In this volume, many notable British and American philosophers unite to honor him and to discuss various topics to which he has contributed significantly. These include general topics in the philosophy of religion such as revelation, and faith and reason, and the specifically Christian doctrines of the Trinity, the Incarnation, and atonement. In the spirit of the movement which Swinburne spearheaded, the essa…Read more
  •  4
    Free To Do Evil
    The Philosophers' Magazine 5 49-51. 1999.
  •  3
    Time and Eternity (review)
    Religious Studies 38 (3): 363-369. 2002.
  • "Alvin Plantinga," edited by James E. Tomberlin and Peter van Inwagen (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (3): 511. 1987.
  • Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32 (3): 314-318. 1981.
  •  208
    Epistemic justification
    Oxford University Press. 2001.
    Richard Swinburne offers an original treatment of a question at the heart of epistemology: what makes a belief rational, or justified in holding? He maps the rival accounts of philosophers on epistemic justification ("internalist" and "externalist"), arguing that they are really accounts of different concepts. He distinguishes between synchronic justification (justification at a time) and diachronic justification (synchronic justification resulting from adequate investigation)--both internalist …Read more
  •  63
    Second reply to grünbaum
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56 (4): 919-925. 2005.
    I give a detailed defence against Grunbaum’s 2004 attack on my Bayesian argument for the existence of God from various features of the universe (its conformity to simple laws, the laws being such as to lead to the evolution of humans, etc.). Theism postulates the simplest possible stopping point for explanation of the various features which I mention, and is such that it makes the accounts of those features more probable than they would be otherwise
  •  20
    Language and Time
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2): 486-489. 1996.
    Part I of Language and Time is a defence of the tensed theory of time, the view that assertions about events happening now or being past or future are irreducible to tenseless assertions about the dates at which events happen or about their occurrence before or after other events. It claims that tensed sentences are not translatable by tenseless sentences, nor do they have the same truth conditions as tenseless sentences. They are reducible in neither of these senses either to tenseless date sen…Read more
  • Argument för Guds existens
    Filosofisk Tidskrift 4. 2007.
  •  95
    The Existence of God
    Oxford University Press UK. 1979.
    Richard Swinburne presents a substantially rewritten and updated edition of his most celebrated book. No other work has made a more powerful case for the probability of the existence of God. Swinburne gives a rigorous and penetrating analysis of the most important arguments for theism: the cosmological argument; arguments from the existence of laws of nature and the 'fine-tuning' of the universe; from the occurrence of consciousness and moral awareness; and from miracles and religious experience…Read more
  •  88
    Discussion. Reply to grünbaum
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (3): 481-485. 2000.