Edinburgh, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
  •  80
    New foundations for practical reasoning
    Minds and Machines 2 (2): 113-144. 1992.
    Practical reasoning aims at deciding what actions to perform in light of the goals a rational agent possesses. This has been a topic of interest in both philosophy and artificial intelligence, but these two disciplines have produced very different models of practical reasoning. The purpose of this paper is to examine each model in light of the other and produce a unified model adequate for the purposes of both disciplines and superior to the standard models employed by either.The philosophical (…Read more
  •  75
    In this book Pollock deals with the subject of probabilistic reasoning, making general philosophical sense of objective probabilities and exploring their ...
  •  74
    The objective of this book is to produce a theory of rational decision making for realistically resource-bounded agents. My interest is not in “What should I do if I were an ideal agent?”, but rather, “What should I do given that I am who I am, with all my actual cognitive limitations?” The book has three parts. Part One addresses the question of where the values come from that agents use in rational decision making. The most comon view among philosophers is that they are based on preferences, b…Read more
  •  70
    A theory of moral reasoning
    Ethics 96 (3): 506-523. 1986.
  •  67
    ``Defeasible Reasoning with Variable Degrees of Justification"
    Artificial Intelligence 133 (1-2): 233-282. 2001.
    The question addressed in this paper is how the degree of justification of a belief is determined. A conclusion may be supported by several different arguments, the arguments typically being defeasible, and there may also be arguments of varying strengths for defeaters for some of the supporting arguments. What is sought is a way of computing the “on sum” degree of justification of a conclusion in terms of the degrees of justification of all relevant premises and the strengths of all relevant re…Read more
  •  64
    "A sequel to Pollock's How to Build a Person, this volume builds upon that theoretical groundwork for the implementation of rationality through artificial ...
  •  64
    Oscar
    Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 6 (1): 89-113. 1996.
    OSCAR is a fully implemented architecture for a cognitive agent, based largely on the author’s work in philosophy concerning epistemology and practical cognition. The seminal idea is that a generally intelligent agent must be able to function in an environment in which it is ignorant of most matters of fact. The architecture incorporates a general-purpose defeasible reasoner, built on top of an efficient natural deduction reasoner for first-order logic. It is based upon a detailed theory about h…Read more
  •  63
    What Am I?
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (2): 237-309. 2008.
    It’s morning. You sit down at your desk, cup of coffee in hand, and prepare to begin your day. First, you turn on your computer. Once it is running, you check your e-mail. Having decided it is all spam, you trash it. You close the window on your e-mail program, but leave the program running so that it will periodically check the mail server to see whether you have new mail. If it finds new mail it will alert you by playing a musical tone. Next you start your word processor. You have in mind to w…Read more
  •  60
    How do you maximize expectation value?
    Noûs 17 (3): 409-421. 1983.
  •  59
    My brother, the machine
    Noûs 22 (2): 173-211. 1988.
  •  57
    Foundations for direct inference
    Theory and Decision 17 (3): 221-255. 1994.
  •  56
    Pollock argues that theories of ideal rationality are largely irrelevant to the decision making of real agents. Thinking about Acting aims to provide a theory of "real rationality.&quot
  •  55
    A problem about frequencies in direct inference
    with Stephen Leeds and Henry E. Kyburg
    Philosophical Studies 48 (1). 1985.
  •  52
    Epistemology and probability
    Synthese 55 (2): 231-252. 1983.
    Probability is sometimes regarded as a universal panacea for epistemology. It has been supposed that the rationality of belief is almost entirely a matter of probabilities. Unfortunately, those philosophers who have thought about this most extensively have tended to be probability theorists first, and epistemologists only secondarily. In my estimation, this has tended to make them insensitive to the complexities exhibited by epistemic justification. In this paper I propose to turn the tables. I …Read more
  •  48
    The logic of projectibility
    Philosophy of Science 39 (3): 302-314. 1972.
    Projectible conditions are (roughly) those whose universal generalizations are con firmed by their positive instances. This paper proposes certain modifications to the above definition in order to capture the pre-analytic notion it is supposed to explicate. Then we investigate what logical operations, when performed on projectible conditionals, yield new projectible conditionals. A number of surprising theorems are proven, and these theorems indicate that few conditionals having complex antecede…Read more
  •  48
    Pollock describes an exciting theory of rationality and its partial implementation in OSCAR, a computer system whose descendants will literally be persons.
  •  46
    Oscar
    Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 6 (1): 89-113. 1996.
    In its present incarnation, OSCAR is a fully implemented programmable architecture for a rational agent. If we just focus upon the epistemic reasoning in OSCAR, we have a powerful general-purpose defeasible reasoner. The purpose of this paper is to describe that reasoner. OSCAR's defeasible reasoner is based upon seven fundamental ideas. These are (1) an argument-based account of defeasible reasoning, (2) an analysis of defeat-status given a set of interrelated arguments, (3) a general adequacy …Read more
  •  44
    Philosophy and AI: Essays at the Interface (edited book)
    MIT Press. 1991.
    Philosophy and AI presents invited contributions that focus on the different perspectives and techniques that philosophy and AI bring to the theory of ...
  •  41
    How to use probabilities in reasoning
    Philosophical Studies 64 (1). 1991.
    Probabilities are important in belief updating, but probabilistic reasoning does not subsume everything else (as the Bayesian would have it). On the contrary, Bayesian reasoning presupposes knowledge that cannot itself be obtained by Bayesian reasoning, making generic Bayesianism an incoherent theory of belief updating. Instead, it is indefinite probabilities that are of principal importance in belief updating. Knowledge of such indefinite probabilities is obtained by some form of statistical in…Read more
  •  39
  •  38
    Counter-induction
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 5 (1-4). 1962.
    This article attempts to show that certain alternatives that have been proposed to the classical principle of induction are necessarily inferior to it. The simplest versions of these ?counter?inductionist? policies are logically inconsistent, and consistent formulations are less reliable than the straight principle of induction
  •  38
    Rationality, function, and content
    Philosophical Studies 65 (1-2): 129-151. 1992.
    To summarize, in order for rational agents to be able to engage in the sophisticated kinds of reasoning exemplified by human beings, they must be able to introspect much of their cognition. The problem of other minds and the problem of knowing the mental states of others will arise automatically for any rational agent that is able to introspect its own cognition. The most that a rational agent can reasonably believe about other rational agents is that they have rational architectures similar to …Read more
  •  34
    Basic modal logic
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (3): 355-365. 1967.
    As anyone who is familiar with the literature knows, there is a great deal of controversy concerning which, if any, of the extant theories of propositional modal logic correctly formalizes the logic of certain logical concepts such as analyticity and logical necessity. Most of the controversy concerns certain principles that involve iterated modalities (where one modal operator occurs within the scope of another). For example, there is considerable disagreement about whether the principle(□p⊃□□p…Read more
  •  34
    Rational Choice and Action Omnipotence
    Philosophical Review 111 (1): 1. 2002.
    A theory of rational choice is a theory of how an agent should, rationally, go about deciding what actions to perform at any given time. For example, I may want to decide whether to go to a movie this evening or stay home and read a book. The actions between which we want to choose are perfectly ordinary actions, and the presumption is that to make such a decision we should attend to the likely consequences of our decision. It is assumed that these decisions must be made in the face of uncertain…Read more
  •  32
    Evaluative cognition
    Noûs 35 (3). 2001.
    Cognitive agents form beliefs representing the world, evaluate the world as represented, form plans for making the world more to their liking, and perform actions executing the plans. Then the cycle repeats. This is the doxastic-conative loop, diagrammed in figure one.1 Both human beings and the autonomous rational agents envisaged in AI are cognitive agents in this sense. The cognition of a cognitive agent can be subdivided into two parts. Epistemic cognition is that kind of cognition responsib…Read more