•  6
    ¿Lo mío y lo tuyo? El Estado kantiano
    Anuario Filosófico 37 (80): 595-630. 2004.
    Kant says there is a duty to exit the state of nature, to enter into a civil state. He says this is a duty of right, not a duty of virtue. The article discusses the argument he gives to support this view, as well as the contemporary discussion on the relationship between this duty of right and the categorical imperative. The discussion is full of implications. Particularly significant is the view of the Kantian state emerging from it, which challenges the conventional account: instead of a state…Read more
  •  50
    Introduction: Scientific History
    with Susanne Hoeber Rudolph
    In his inaugural lecture at Cambridge as Regius Professor of Modern History in 1895, Lord Acton urged that the historian deliver moral judgments on the figures of his research. Acton declaimed: I exhort you never to debase the moral currency or to lower the standard of rectitude, but to try others by the final maxim that governs your own lives and to suffer no man and no cause to escape the undying penalty which history has the power to inflict on wrong.1 In 1902, the year after Acton died, the …Read more
  •  120
    Hegel’s Original Insight
    International Philosophical Quarterly 33 (3): 285-295. 1993.
  •  5
    Précis
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 73 (3): 309-312. 2015.
  •  46
    Hegel and Institutional Rationality
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 39 (S1): 1-25. 2001.
  •  55
    Avoiding German Idealism
    Proceedings of the Eighth International Kant Congress 1 977-997. 1995.
  •  208
    Kant on the Spontaneity of Mind
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (2). 1987.
    In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant refers often and with no apparent hesitation or sense of ambiguity to the mind. He does so not only in his justly famous destruction of rationalist proofs of immaterialism, but throughout his own, positive, ‘transcendental’ account in the Transcendental Aesthetic and Transcendental Analytic. In the first edition of the Critique, he even proposed what he adventurously called a ‘transcendental psychology’ and, although this strange discipline seemed to disappea…Read more
  •  103
    The Significance of Self‐Consciousness in Idealist Theories of Logic
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 114 (2pt2): 145-166. 2014.
    Among Kant's innovations in the understanding of logic (‘general logic’) were his claims that logic had no content of its own, but was the form of the thought of any possible content, and that the unit of meaning, the truth-bearer, judgement, was essentially apperceptive. Judging was implicitly the consciousness of judging. This was for Kant a logical truth. This article traces the influence of the latter claim on Fichte, and, for most of the discussion, on Hegel. The aim is to understand the re…Read more
  •  101
    Hegel's metaphysics and the problem of contradiction
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 16 (3): 301-312. 1978.
  •  3
    Brusotti, Marco (1997b). “Erkenntnis als Passion: Nietzsches Denkweg zwischen Morgenröte und der Fröhliche Wissenschaft,” Nietzsche-Studien, Band 26 (1997), 199-225.
  •  8
    Forthcoming in Conference Proceedings, Jena Phänomenologie conference I Hegels Charakterisierungen der neuen, von ihm entwickelten philosophischen Form, der Phänomenologie des Geistes, stellen vor allem deswegen ein Problem dar, weil sie so zahlreich sind. Bei einigen handelt es sich um klar erkennbare Reformulierungen oder Spezifizierungen anderer, in vielen Fällen aber scheinen die Beschreibungen inkonsistent zu sein oder unterschiedliche Perioden in Hegels Denken widerzuspiegeln, das sich wäh…Read more
  •  14
    Brandom's Hegel (review)
    European Journal of Philosophy 13 (3): 381-408. 2005.
  •  7
    Bernard Williams once made the interesting point that both Wittgenstein and Nietzsche were trying to say something about what it might mean for philosophy to come to an end, for a culture to be cured of philosophy. He meant the end of philosophical theory, the idea that unaided human reason could contribute to knowledge about substance, being, our conceptual scheme, the highest values, the meaning of history or the way language works. For both Wittgenstein and Nietzsche there is no good or modes…Read more
  •  51
    The Persistence of Subjectivity examines several approaches to, and critiques of, the core notion in the self-understanding and legitimation of the modern, 'bourgeois' form of life: the free, reflective, self-determining subject. Since it is a relatively recent historical development that human beings think of themselves as individual centers of agency, and that one's entitlement to such a self-determining life is absolutely valuable, the issue at stake also involves the question of the historic…Read more
  •  76
    In the most influential chapter of his most important philosophical work, the Phenomenology of Spirit, Hegel makes the central and disarming assertions that "self-consciousness is desire itself" and that it attains its "satisfaction" only in another self-consciousness. Hegel on Self-Consciousness presents a groundbreaking new interpretation of these revolutionary claims, tracing their roots to Kant's philosophy and demonstrating their continued relevance for contemporary thought. As Robert Pippi…Read more
  •  5
    Kant and the Claims of Knowledge (review) (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 28 (1): 138-141. 1990.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:138 JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 28:1 JANUARY 1990 Paul Guyer. Kant and the Claims of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987. Pp. xiii + 482. Cloth, $59.5 o. Paper, $x9.95. For several years now, Paul Guyer has been publishing articles on what he sees as numerous different strategies pursued by Kant in his attempt to deduce the objective validity of pure categories. In this very long, extremely detailed book, …Read more
  •  66
    Hegel's Dialectic: The Explanation of Possibility
    Philosophical Review 100 (4): 710. 1991.