•  71
    Meinong's Theory of Sense and Reference
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 50 (1): 171-186. 1995.
    Gilbert Ryle wrote that "Meaning-theory expanded just when and just in so far as it was released from that 'Fido'-Fido box, the lid of which was never even lifted by Meinong". This paper sets out to relieve Ryle's oversimplification about Meinong and the role of meaning theory in his thought. One step away from canine simplicity about meaning is the recognition of a distinction between sense and reference, such as we find in Frege, Husserl, and the early Russell. In Über Möglichkeit und Wahrsche…Read more
  •  71
    The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics (edited book)
    with Robin Le Poidevin, McGonigal Andrew, and Ross P. Cameron
    Routledge. 2009.
    The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics is an outstanding, comprehensive and accessible guide to the major themes, thinkers, and issues in metaphysics. The Companion features over fifty specially commissioned chapters from international scholars which are organized into three clear parts: History of Metaphysics Ontology Metaphysics and Science. Each section features an introduction which places the range of essays in context, while an extensive glossary allows easy reference to key terms and defi…Read more
  •  70
    Logical atomism and its ontological refinement: A defense
    In Kevin Mulligan (ed.), Language, Truth and Ontology, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 157--179. 1992.
  •  70
    Mind and opacity
    Dialectica 49 (2-4): 131-46. 1995.
    Where there is mind there is representational opacity, and vice versa. Opacity arises because where there is representation there may be misrepresentation, and the status of the misrepresenting sign or state of the misrepresenting sign‐user can only be characterized via the terms used for a correctly represented object. Opacity is not a blight for naturalism, but must be recognized and exploited if naturalism is to adequately embrace the mental. Opacity is illustrated for language, for the menta…Read more
  •  70
    Against the aggregate theory of number
    Journal of Philosophy 79 (3): 163-167. 1982.
  •  68
    Unsaturatedness
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 14 (1): 73-95. 1981.
    Frege's obscure key concept of the unsaturatedness of functions is clarified with the help of the concepts of dependent and independent parts and foundation relations used by Husserl in describing the ontology of complex wholes. Sentential unity in Frege, Husserl and Wittgenstein: all have a similar explanation. As applied to linguistic expressions, the terms 'unsaturated' and 'incomplete' are ambiguous: they may mean the ontological property of Unselbständigkeit, inability to exist alone, or th…Read more
  •  67
    I_– _Peter Simons
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 (1): 59-75. 2000.
  •  62
    Vagueness and Ignorance
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 66 (1): 145-178. 1992.
  •  62
    In a recent article, Herbert Hochberg portrays my ontological position, that of a trope nominalist who is sceptical about relational tropes, as deviating into idealism. Since there are few philosophical views I find more repugnant than idealism, I must either resist the accusation or recant. I choose to resist, by showing how relational tropes are not needed as truth-makers for a wide range of truths, and raising the real possibility that they may not be needed at all, without lapsing into eithe…Read more
  •  61
  •  57
    Abstraction, Structure, and Substitution
    Polish Journal of Philosophy 1 (1): 81-100. 2007.
    λ-calculi are of interest to logicians and computer scientists but have largely escaped philosophical commentary, perhaps because they appear narrowly technical or uncontroversial or both. I argue that even within logic λ-expressions need to be understood correctly, as functors signifying functions in intension within a categorical or typed language. λ-expressions are not names but pure viable binders generating functors, and as such they are of use in giving explicit definitions. But λ is appli…Read more
  •  57
    Class, mass and mereology
    History and Philosophy of Logic 4 (1-2): 157-180. 1983.
    LeSniewski?s systems of Ontology and Mereology, considered from a purely formal point of view, possessstriking algebraic parallels, ascan be seen in their respective relations to Boolean algebra. But there are alsoimportant divergences, above all that general Mereology is silent, where Ontology is not, on the existenceof ?atoms? (individuals). By employing plural terms, LeSniewski sought to accommodate talk of (distributive)classes, without according these an autonomous ontological status. His l…Read more
  •  56
    Bolzano's Monadology
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23 (6): 1074-1084. 2015.
    Bernard Bolzano, known in his lifetime as ‘the Bohemian Leibniz’, is best known as a logician and mathematician, but he also developed a monadology in which the monads, which he called ‘atoms’, have spatial location and physical properties. This essay summarizes and assesses his monadology
  •  56
    Stanisław leśniewski
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  55
    Tractatus Mereologico-Philosophicus?
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 28 (1): 165-186. 1986.
    The philosophies of late Brentano and early Wittgenstein can be brought closer in two ways. One way discovers a surprising amount of part-whole theory in the Tractatus if we see states of affairs (not wholly wilfully) as thinglike rather than factlike. This throws up a modal analogue to Chisholm's entia successiva in the form of situations. The other way sees all propositions as truth-functions of existential propositions, supporting Brentano's view that existentials are primary, and incidentall…Read more
  •  53
    Unkindly coincidences
    Mind 95 (380): 506-509. 1986.
  •  52
    Husserl and Frege (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 34 (136): 420. 1984.
  •  52
    L'axe analytique anglo-autrichien
    RÉPHA, revue étudiante de philosophie analytique 4 5-32. 2011.
  •  50
    Continuants and Occurrents
    with Joseph Melia
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 59-92. 2000.
    Commonsense ontology contains both continuants and occurrents, but are continuants necessary? I argue that they are neither occurrents nor easily replaceable by them. The worst problem for continuants is the question in virtue of what a given continuant exists at a given time. For such truthmakers we must have recourse to occurrents, those vital to the continuant at that time. Continuants are, like abstract objects, invariants under equivalences over occurrents. But they are not abstract, and th…Read more
  •  48
    Tree proofs for syllogistic
    Studia Logica 48 (4). 1989.
    This paper presents a tree method for testing the validity of inferences, including syllogisms, in a simple term logic. The method is given in the form of an algorithm and is shown to be sound and complete with respect to the obvious denotational semantics. The primitive logical constants of the system, which is indebted to the logical works of Jevons, Brentano and Lewis Carroll, are term negation, polyadic term conjunction, and functors affirming and denying existence, and use is also made of a…Read more
  •  48
    Existential Propositions
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 42 (1): 229-259. 1992.
    By considering a wide and expressly classified range of examples from natural and logical languages, the attempt is made to isolate from other concomitants the features of existential sentences which make them existential. One such concomitant is the imputation of singularity. There are many ways to say something exists, and their relationships are charted. It is denied that there is anything in reality called existence, or any special existential facts.
  •  47
    Truth-maker optimalism
    Logique Et Analyse 43 (169-170): 17-41. 2000.
  •  46
    New Categories for Formal Ontology
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 49 (1): 77-99. 1994.
    What primitive concepts does formal ontology require? Forsaking as too indirect the linguistic way of discerning the categories of being, this paper considers what primitives might be required for representing things in themselves (noumena) and representations of them in a thoroughly crafted large autonomous multi-purpose database. Leaving logical concepts and material ontology aside, the resulting 32 categories in 13 families range from the obvious (identity/difference, existence/non-existence)…Read more
  •  45
    Pointers
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 94 (3): 381-390. 2017.
    _ Source: _Volume 94, Issue 3, pp 381 - 390 Reference can fail in a way that intentionality cannot. Though the stream of phenomenal experience typically does not fail to target objects outside, it may do. How does the mind go about targeting objects beyond itself? The speculative conjecture of this paper is that it does so by a type of process which can be called _pointing_, and that the acts or act-aspects of pointing can be called _pointers_. The notion of a pointer has several suggestive root…Read more
  •  44
    Mereology and truth-making
    Logic and Logical Philosophy 25 (3): 245-258. 2016.
    Many mereological propositions are true contingently, so we are entitled to ask why they are true. One frequently given type of answer to such questions evokes truth-makers, that is, entities in virtue of whose existence the propositions in question are true. However, even without endorsing the extreme view that all contingent propositions have truth-makers, it turns out to be puzzlingly hard to provide intuitively convincing candidate truth-makers for even a core class of basic mereological pro…Read more
  •  42
    Extended Simples
    The Monist 87 (3): 371-384. 2004.
    I argue that the assumptions that physically basic things are either mereologically atomic, or that they are continuous and there are no atoms, both face difficult conceptual problems. Both views tend to presuppose a largely unquestioned assumption, that things have parts corresponding to the geometric parts of the regions they occupy. To avoid these problems I propose a third view, that physically simple things occupy a finite volume without themselves having parts. This view is examined enough…Read more
  •  42
    Parts: A Study in Ontology
    Clarendon Press. 1987.
    The relationship of part to whole is one of the most fundamental there is; this is the first and only full-length study of this concept. This book shows that mereology, the formal theory of part and whole, is essential to ontology. Peter Simons surveys and criticizes previous theories, especially the standard extensional view, and proposes a more adequate account which encompasses both temporal and modal considerations in detail. 'Parts could easily be the standard book on mereology for the next…Read more