•  132
    This Article does not have an abstract
  • Austrian philosophers on truth
    In Markus Textor (ed.), The Austrian Contribution to Analytic Philosophy, Routledge. pp. 1--159. 2006.
    In this chapter, I shall consider what the principal Austrian philosophers from Bolzano to Popper have had to say on the subject of truth. Since I shall cover a fair number of philosophers and theories, my considerations will be mainly confined to two linked questions: What – according to the philosopher in question – is the nature of truth? What ontology is required to explicate truth according to their account? Further questions concerned with our access to and knowledge of the truth will only…Read more
  • Die verlorene Welt
    Ethik Und Sozialwissenschaften 3 (2): 164. 1992.
  •  71
    Meinong's Theory of Sense and Reference
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 50 (1): 171-186. 1995.
    Gilbert Ryle wrote that "Meaning-theory expanded just when and just in so far as it was released from that 'Fido'-Fido box, the lid of which was never even lifted by Meinong". This paper sets out to relieve Ryle's oversimplification about Meinong and the role of meaning theory in his thought. One step away from canine simplicity about meaning is the recognition of a distinction between sense and reference, such as we find in Frege, Husserl, and the early Russell. In Über Möglichkeit und Wahrsche…Read more
  •  19
    Truth in virtue of meaning
    In Jean-Maurice Monnoyer (ed.), Metaphysics and Truthmakers, Ontos Verlag. pp. 67-78. 2007.
  •  11
    Erratum
    Philosophia Mathematica. forthcoming.
    Rafal Urbaniak. Leśniewski’s Systems of Logic and Foundations of Mathematics. Trends in Logic; 37. Springer, 2014. ISBN: 978-3-319-00481-5, 978-3-319-34416-4, 978-3-319-00482-2. Pp. xiii + 229.
  •  56
    Stanisław leśniewski
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  • Whitehead : process and cosmology
    In Robin Le Poidevin, Simons Peter, McGonigal Andrew & Ross P. Cameron (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics, Routledge. 2009.
  •  36
    Linguistic Complexity and Argumentative Unity: A Lvov-Warsaw School Supplement
    Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 36 (1): 101-119. 2014.
    It is argued that the source of complexity in language is twofold: repetition, and syntactic embedding. The former enables us to return again and again to the same subject across many sentences, and to maintain the coherence of an argument. The latter is governed by two forms of complexification: the functor-argument structure of all languages and the operator-bound-variable mechanism of familiar formal languages. The former is most transparently represented by categorial grammar, and an extensi…Read more
  •  61
    In a recent article, Herbert Hochberg portrays my ontological position, that of a trope nominalist who is sceptical about relational tropes, as deviating into idealism. Since there are few philosophical views I find more repugnant than idealism, I must either resist the accusation or recant. I choose to resist, by showing how relational tropes are not needed as truth-makers for a wide range of truths, and raising the real possibility that they may not be needed at all, without lapsing into eithe…Read more
  •  10
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 101 (403): 581-582. 1992.
  •  14
    The Thread of Persistence
    In Kanzian Christian (ed.), Persistence, Ontos. pp. 165-184. 2007.
  •  42
    Parts: A Study in Ontology
    Clarendon Press. 1987.
    The relationship of part to whole is one of the most fundamental there is; this is the first and only full-length study of this concept. This book shows that mereology, the formal theory of part and whole, is essential to ontology. Peter Simons surveys and criticizes previous theories, especially the standard extensional view, and proposes a more adequate account which encompasses both temporal and modal considerations in detail. 'Parts could easily be the standard book on mereology for the next…Read more
  •  482
    Bocheński and balance: System and history in analytic philosophy
    Studies in East European Thought 55 (4): 281-297. 2003.
    Using the work of Józef Bocheski as apositive example, this paper sets out the casefor a balanced use of historical knowledge indoing analytic philosophy. Between the twoextremes of relativizing historicism, whichdenies absolute truth, and arrogant scientism,which denies any constructive role for thehistory of ideas in philosophy, lies a viamedia in which historical reflection onconcepts and their history is placed at theservice of the system of cognitive philosophy.Knowledge of the history of p…Read more
  •  48
    Existential Propositions
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 42 (1): 229-259. 1992.
    By considering a wide and expressly classified range of examples from natural and logical languages, the attempt is made to isolate from other concomitants the features of existential sentences which make them existential. One such concomitant is the imputation of singularity. There are many ways to say something exists, and their relationships are charted. It is denied that there is anything in reality called existence, or any special existential facts.
  •  20
    New Categories for Formal Ontology
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 49 (1): 77-99. 1994.
    What primitive concepts does formal ontology require? Forsaking as too indirect the linguistic way of discerning the categories of being, this paper considers what primitives might be required for representing things in themselves (noumena) and representations of them in a thoroughly crafted large autonomous multi-purpose database. Leaving logical concepts and material ontology aside, the resulting 32 categories in 13 families range from the obvious (identity/difference, existence/non-existence)…Read more
  • A Note on Le'sniewski and Free Logic
    Logique Et Analyse 24 (95): 415-420. 1981.
  •  23
    The Next Best Thing to Sense in Begriffsschrift
    In Petr Kotatko & John Biro (eds.), Frege: Sense and Reference One Hundred Years Later, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 129--140. 1995.
  •  103
    Confounding earlier predictions of naysayers and sceptics, by the beginning of the twenty-first century, metaphysics had re-emerged for the first time in decades as a vital, progressive and exciting branch of philosophy. Although the most strident criticisms came from early analytic philosophers such as Carnap, it is analytical metaphysics that has led the way. But rather than trace the stages of the revival of metaphysics, we consider a spread of contemporary themes which have been especially f…Read more
  •  1
    Formal Ontology
    with Roberto Poli
    Studia Logica 64 (3): 410-413. 2000.
  •  34
    To be and/or not to be the objects of meinong and Husserl
    In Lila Haaparanta & Heikki Koskinen (eds.), Categories of Being: Essays on Metaphysics and Logic, Oxford University Press, Usa. pp. 241. 2012.
  •  119
    Ontology Meets Ontologies: Philosophers as Healers (review)
    Metascience 18 (3): 469-473. 2009.
  •  77
    Leibniz, Whitehead and the Metaphysics of Causation
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18 (1): 175-177. 2010.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  220
    Ramsey, Particulars, and Universals
    Theoria 57 (3): 150-161. 1991.
    My subject is the arguments brought by Ramsey in his paper “ Universals ” ’ against the generally held distinction between particulars and universals. This paper is provocative, suggestive, and radical, and it is humbling to reflect that its author was just 22 years old when it was published in Mind. As so often with Ramsey, the paper is superficially very easy to follow and hardly requires any introduction other than the imperative, “Read it through”, but underneath the surface are many assumpt…Read more
  •  20
    Continuants and Occurrents, I
    Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 74 (1): 59-75. 2000.