University of Michigan, Ann Arbor
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1974
College Park, Maryland, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Metaphysics
Aesthetics
  •  112
    The Aesthetic Appreciation of Music
    British Journal of Aesthetics 49 (4): 415-425. 2009.
    This essay offers a sketch of what aesthetic appreciation of music fundamentally consists in, underlining both why such engagement counts as aesthetic and why such engagement counts as appreciation, and emphasizing the role of perception of gesture in the grasp of musical expressiveness. The analysis is illustrated by a piece of chamber music of Gabriel Fauré. In the last section of the essay I address some remarks of Roger Scruton on the connection between music and dance, ones whose relevance …Read more
  •  105
    Properties and related entities
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 39 (1): 1-22. 1978.
  •  101
    The particularisation of attributes
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58 (2). 1980.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  100
    Being realistic about aesthetic properties
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (3): 351-354. 1994.
  •  92
    Zemach on paintings
    British Journal of Aesthetics 27 (3): 278-283. 1987.
  •  92
    A note on categorical properties and contingent identity
    Journal of Philosophy 85 (12): 718-722. 1988.
    Stephen Yablo has attempted recently to revive the notion of contingent identity, identifying this with a relation of L coincidence between objects that are "distinct by nature but the same in the circumstances" (296). Yablo argues convincingly for the need of essentialist metaphysics to recognize some relation of this sort, a relation of "intimate identity-like connections between things" (296) if it is to acknowledge properly the intuitive difference between (i) the nonidentity of a bust B and…Read more
  •  88
    The irreducible historicality of the concept of art
    British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (4): 367-379. 2002.
    In this short paper I begin by underlining the sense in which my intentional-historical theory of art, first proposed in 1979, attributes to art a certain irreducible historicality. I next defend the theory, in broad outline, against a number of objections that have been raised against it in the past ten years. I conclude with some remarks on the similarities and differences between ordinary artefact concepts and the concept of an artwork.
  •  84
    Narration in Light: Studies in Cinematic Point of View
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 47 (3): 290-292. 1989.
  •  81
    Autographic and allographic art revisited
    Philosophical Studies 38 (4). 1980.
  •  80
    Sexual Perversity
    The Monist 86 (1): 30-54. 2003.
    Ivan is a gifted pianist, but spends most of his time at the keyboard playing simple blues progressions over and over. Sarah is fluent in French, but avoids every opportunity to converse in that language. Greg lives in a household whose kitchen offers an assortment of tantalizing foods, yet he never eats anything except bagels and cream cheese. Melinda has many friends, with whom she would enjoy socializing, but she forgoes their company to devote all her free time to video games. Clive is a cha…Read more
  •  79
    Hybrid Art Forms
    Journal of Aesthetic Education 18 (4): 5-14. 1984.
  •  75
    What Is a Temporal Art?
    with Philip Alperson
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 16 (1): 439-450. 1991.
  •  74
    Art historically defined: Reply to Oppy
    British Journal of Aesthetics 33 (4): 380-385. 1993.
  •  74
    Music in the moment
    Cornell University Press. 1997.
    Does aural understanding depend upon reflective awareness of musical architecture or large-scale musical structure? Jerrold Levinson thinks not.
  •  69
    Extending art historically
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (3): 411-423. 1993.
  •  69
    Music-Specific Emotion: An Elusive Quarry
    Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 53 (2): 115-131. 2016.
    Expressive music, almost everyone agrees, evokes an emotional response of some kind in receptive listeners, at least some of the time, in at least some conditions of listening. But is such an emotional response distinctive of or unique to the music that evokes it? In other words, is there such a thing as music-specific emotion? This essay is devoted to an exploration of that question and others related to it. In the main part of the essay a sixpart component model of a standard emotion is set ou…Read more
  •  67
    Peter Kivy and the Philosophy of Music
    British Journal of Aesthetics 57 (3): 269-282. 2017.
    In the beginning—or more exactly, the seventies, when I was in graduate school at the University of Michigan—was the void, and darkness was upon the face of the waters. Philosophical reflection on the experience, meaning, and powers of music by analytic philosophers was almost non-existent. And then, as the 1980s dawned, came Peter Kivy. Suddenly there was light, and analytic philosophy of music was born. In this piece I summarize the substance of the successive instalments in the astounding ser…Read more
  •  64
    The real problem sustained: Reply to Wieand
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 61 (4). 2003.
  •  63
    Colourization ill-defended
    British Journal of Aesthetics 30 (1): 62-67. 1990.
  •  57
    Aesthetic uniqueness
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 38 (4): 435-449. 1980.
  •  57
    Musical profundity misplaced
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50 (1): 58-60. 1992.
  •  56
    Gewirth on absolute rights
    Philosophical Quarterly 32 (126): 73-75. 1982.
  •  56
    Reply to Nicholas Riggle's “Levinson on the Aesthetic Ideal”
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 71 (3): 281-282. 2013.
  •  54
    Truth in music
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 40 (2): 131-144. 1981.
  •  54
    Concatenationism, Architectonicism, and the Appreciation of Music
    Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4 (4): 505-514. 2006.
  •  52
    Jazz Vocal Interpretation: A Philosophical Analysis
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 71 (1): 35-43. 2013.
  •  49
    Contextualisme esthétique
    Philosophiques 32 (1): 125-133. 2005.
    Je me fixe deux objectifs dans ce texte. Le premier est de situer l’esthétique ou la philosophie de l’art par rapport à la philosophie en général et d’expliquer pourquoi elle a été la préoccupation centrale de tant de philosophes dans la tradition. Mon second objectif est de définir un courant dominant de l’esthétique des trente dernières années, que je nomme « contextualisme », et d’expliquer son importance en ce qui concerne les réflexions des artistes, critiques, théoriciens et publics à prop…Read more
  •  48
    Who's Afraid Of A Paraphrase?
    Theoria 67 (1): 7-23. 2001.
    I first show why Davidson was wrong to maintain that there is no such thing as metaphorical meaning, that which paraphrases strive to capture. I then sketch a conception of metaphors as utterances in contexts, and suggest how such utterances can acquire metaphorical meanings despite there being no semantic rules for the projection of such meanings. I next urge the essentiality of a metaphor's verbal formulation to its being the metaphor it is, and I conclude with some reflections on common and u…Read more
  •  47
    Universals: An Opinionated Introduction
    with D. M. Armstrong
    Philosophical Review 101 (3): 654. 1992.