University of Michigan, Ann Arbor
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1974
College Park, Maryland, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Metaphysics
Aesthetics
  •  45
    Musical thinking
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 27 (1). 2003.
  •  44
    Making Believe
    Dialogue 32 (2): 359-. 1993.
    Kendall Walton's Mimesis as Make-Believe is the most significant event in Anglo-American aesthetics in many a year, and joins a small pantheon of landmark books such as Nelson Goodman's Languages of Art, Richard Wollheim's Art and Its Objects and Arthur Danto's Transfiguration of the Commonplace. Walton's aim is to provide a comprehensive account of the representational arts—literature, drama, cinema, painting, drawing, sculpture—from both the generative and the receptive points of view. That is…Read more
  •  42
    Philosophy as an Art
    The Journal of Aesthetic Education 24 (2): 5. 1990.
  •  42
    Popular Song as Moral Microcosm: Life Lessons from Jazz Standards
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 71 51-66. 2012.
    In a recent paper devoted to my topic, music and morality, my fellow philosopher of music Peter Kivy makes a helpful tripartite distinction among ways in which music could be said to have moral force. The first is by embodying and conveying moral insight; Kivy labels that epistemic moral force. The second is by having a positive moral effect on behavior; Kivy labels that behavioral moral force. And the third is by impacting positively on character so as to make someone a better human being; Kivy…Read more
  •  38
    An Ontology of Art, by Gregory Currie (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1): 215-222. 1992.
  •  37
    Suffering Art Gladly: The Paradox of Negative Emotions in Art (edited book)
    Palgrave/Macmillan. 2013.
    Suffering Art Gladly is concerned with the ostensibly paradoxical phenomenon of negative emotions involved in the experience of art: how can we explain the pleasure felt or satisfaction taken in such experience when it is the vehicle of negative emotions, that is, ones that seem to be unpleasant or undesirable, and that one normally tries to avoid experiencing? The question is as old as philosophical reflection on the arts, beginning with Plato and Aristotle, and subsequently addressed by Hume, …Read more
  •  37
    Seeing, imaginarily, at the movies
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (170): 70-78. 1994.
  •  37
    Beauty is Not One: The Irreducible Variety of Visual Beauty
    In Elisabeth Schellekens & Peter Goldie (eds.), The Aesthetic Mind: Philosophy and Psychology, Oxford University Press. pp. 190-207. 2011.
  •  35
    Film Music and Narrative Agency
    In David Bordwell Noel Carroll (ed.), Post-Theory: Reconstructing Film Studies, U Wisconsin Press. 1996.
  •  33
    The Aesthetics of Music (review)
    Philosophical Review 109 (4): 608-614. 2000.
    As readers of this book will discover, from several disputes with me contained in its pages, Scruton and I are not in accord on a number of matters in the philosophy of music. Notwithstanding that, and more generally the fact that the book is controlled by a phenomenological-idealist perspective on music that I regard as fundamentally misplaced, in my estimation The Aesthetics of Music is the most valuable work to date on the subject of its title, one that addresses that subject in its full rang…Read more
  •  30
    Evaluating Musical Performance
    The Journal of Aesthetic Education 21 (1): 75. 1987.
  •  29
    Truth, Fiction, and Literature (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4): 964-968. 1997.
  •  29
    Titoli
    Aisthesis: Pratiche, Linguaggi E Saperi Dell’Estetico 4 (2). 2011.
  •  29
    Nonexistent Objects
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 40 (1): 96-99. 1980.
  •  29
    Film, Art, and the Third Culture
    British Journal of Aesthetics 58 (3): 336-341. 2018.
    Film, Art, and the Third CultureSmithMurrayoup. 2017. pp. 320. £35.00.
  •  27
    An Ontology of Art, by Gregory Currie (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1): 215-222. 1992.
  •  26
    Indication, abstraction, and individuation
    In Christy Mag Uidhir (ed.), Art and Abstract Objects, Oxford University Press. pp. 49. 2013.
  •  25
    Le son musical est vibration, et dépend des instruments utilisés. Être fidèle aux instruments prévus par le compositeur ne répond pas à un simple souci d’authenticité. Notre écoute de l’œuvre musicale dépend des gestes instrumentaux pratiqués par les musiciens (gestes que nous voyons au concert, ou que nous supposons si la musique est enregistrée). Les gestes proprement musicaux (liés à l’expressivité de la musique) sont fonction des gestes effectifs pratiqués par l’instrumentiste. Chaque instru…Read more
  •  24
    Musical Literacy
    The Journal of Aesthetic Education 24 (1): 17. 1990.
  •  23
    The Aesthetics of Music (review)
    Philosophical Review 109 (4): 608-614. 2000.
    As readers of this book will discover, from several disputes with me contained in its pages, Scruton and I are not in accord on a number of matters in the philosophy of music. Notwithstanding that, and more generally the fact that the book is controlled by a phenomenological-idealist perspective on music that I regard as fundamentally misplaced, in my estimation The Aesthetics of Music is the most valuable work to date on the subject of its title, one that addresses that subject in its full rang…Read more
  •  22
    Truth, Fiction, and Literature (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4): 964-968. 1997.
  •  22
    Music and Negative Emotion
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 63 (4): 327-346. 1982.
  •  21
    An Error Concerning Noses
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 75 (1): 9-13. 2017.
    We identify a strategy for getting beliefs from fiction via three assumptions: a certain causal generality holds in the fiction and does so because causal generalities in fiction are carried over from what the author takes to be fact; the author is reliable on this topic, so what the author takes to be fact is fact. We do not question. While will, in particular cases, be doubtful, the strategy is vulnerable more generally to the worry that what looks like a causal generality may be instead an au…Read more
  •  20
    Refining Art Historically
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 47 (1): 21-33. 1989.
  •  19
    Aesthetic Supervenience
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 22 (S1): 93-110. 1984.
  •  18
    Causal history, actual and apparent
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (2). 2013.
    Attention is drawn to the distinction between the actual (or factual) and the apparent (or ostensible) causal history of a work of art, and how the authors' recommendation in the name of understanding works of art blurs that distinction, thus inadvertently reinforcing the hoary idea, against which the authors otherwise rightly battle, that what one needs to properly appreciate an artwork can be found in even suitably framed observation of the work alone
  •  18
    Introduction
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62 (2): 89-93. 2004.
    Jerrold Levinson; Introduction, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Volume 62, Issue 2, 5 May 2004, Pages 89–93, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-594X.20.
  •  17
    Artist and Aesthete: A Dual Portrait
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 75 (4): 479-487. 2017.
    Two of the principal roles or positions in the aesthetic/artistic situation are those of artist and aesthete. The former is obviously primarily a creative role, while the latter is obviously primarily an appreciative role. And these roles, as we know, are also interdependent: aesthetes would have little, or at any rate less, to appreciate without artists, while artists would have little, or at any rate less, creative motivation without appreciators, with aesthetes as the most important vanguard …Read more