University of Michigan, Ann Arbor
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1974
College Park, Maryland, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Metaphysics
Aesthetics
  •  13
    Musical Concerns: Essays in Philosophy of Music
    Oxford University Press. 2015.
    This volume presents a new collection of essays on music by Jerrold Levinson, one of the most prominent philosophers of art today. The essays are wide-ranging and represent some of the most stimulating work being done within analytic aesthetics. Three of the essays are previously unpublished, and four of them focus on music in the jazz tradition.
  •  38
    Suffering Art Gladly: The Paradox of Negative Emotions in Art (edited book)
    Palgrave/Macmillan. 2013.
    Suffering Art Gladly is concerned with the ostensibly paradoxical phenomenon of negative emotions involved in the experience of art: how can we explain the pleasure felt or satisfaction taken in such experience when it is the vehicle of negative emotions, that is, ones that seem to be unpleasant or undesirable, and that one normally tries to avoid experiencing? The question is as old as philosophical reflection on the arts, beginning with Plato and Aristotle, and subsequently addressed by Hume, …Read more
  •  100
    Being realistic about aesthetic properties
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (3): 351-354. 1994.
  •  123
    This is a long-awaited reissue of Jerrold Levinson's 1990 book which gathers together the writings that made him a leading figure in contemporary aesthetics. These highly influential essays are essential reading for debates on the definition of art, the ontology of art, emotional response to art, expression in art, and the nature of art forms.
  •  13
    Aesthetic Supervenience
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 22 (S1): 93-110. 1984.
  •  1336
    What a musical work is
    Journal of Philosophy 77 (1): 5-28. 1980.
  • Il piacere nella musica contemporanea
    Discipline Filosofiche 15 (2). 2005.
  • Peter Kivy, Sound and Semblance (review)
    Philosophy in Review 5 454-459. 1985.
  •  184
    Aesthetic Supervenience
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 22 (S1): 93-110. 1984.
  •  302
    The Oxford handbook of aesthetics (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2003.
    The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics brings the authority, liveliness, and multi-disciplinary scope of the Handbook series to a fascinating theme in philosophy and the arts. Jerrold Levinson has assembled a hugely impressive range of talent to contribute 48 brand-new essays, making this the most comprehensive guide available to the theory, application, history, and future of the field. This Handbook will be invaluable to academics and students across philosophy and all branches of the arts, both as…Read more
  •  35
    Film Music and Narrative Agency
    In David Bordwell Noel Carroll (ed.), Post-Theory: Reconstructing Film Studies, U Wisconsin Press. 1996.
  •  334
    Philosophy and music
    Topoi 28 (2): 119-123. 2009.
    This essay explores some aspects of the relation between philosophy and music. First, how music can inspire philosophy; second, how philosophy can inspire music. Mathematics as a middle term between music and philosophy, the idea of wholeness in a musical composition or a philosophical text, music as a mode of thought displaying traits such as logic, coherence, and sense—these are some ways in which music and philosophy may be seen to be connected. Also, composers sometimes have explicit recours…Read more
  •  70
    Extending art historically
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (3): 411-423. 1993.
  • Music in the Moment
    Philosophical Quarterly 49 (196): 403-405. 1999.
  •  75
    What Is a Temporal Art?
    with Philip Alperson
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 16 (1): 439-450. 1991.
  •  29
    Titoli
    Aisthesis: Pratiche, Linguaggi E Saperi Dell’Estetico 4 (2). 2011.
  •  18
    Causal history, actual and apparent
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (2). 2013.
    Attention is drawn to the distinction between the actual (or factual) and the apparent (or ostensible) causal history of a work of art, and how the authors' recommendation in the name of understanding works of art blurs that distinction, thus inadvertently reinforcing the hoary idea, against which the authors otherwise rightly battle, that what one needs to properly appreciate an artwork can be found in even suitably framed observation of the work alone
  •  23
    Music and Negative Emotion
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 63 (4): 327-346. 1982.
  •  3
    An Ontology of Art, by Gregory Currie (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1): 215-222. 1992.
  •  13
    Why There Are No Tropes
    Philosophy 81 (4): 563-580. 2006.
    This paper effectively inverts the argument of an earlier paper of mine, “The Particularisation of Attributes”, to argue that there are no necessarily particularised and unshareable attributes of the sort that contemporary metaphysics calls tropes. In that earlier paper I distinguished two kinds of attributes, namely, properties and qualities, and argued that if there were tropes they could only be particularised qualities, i.e. particularisations of, say, redness, rather than particularisations…Read more
  •  25
    Le son musical est vibration, et dépend des instruments utilisés. Être fidèle aux instruments prévus par le compositeur ne répond pas à un simple souci d’authenticité. Notre écoute de l’œuvre musicale dépend des gestes instrumentaux pratiqués par les musiciens (gestes que nous voyons au concert, ou que nous supposons si la musique est enregistrée). Les gestes proprement musicaux (liés à l’expressivité de la musique) sont fonction des gestes effectifs pratiqués par l’instrumentiste. Chaque instru…Read more
  •  42
    Popular Song as Moral Microcosm: Life Lessons from Jazz Standards
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 71 51-66. 2012.
    In a recent paper devoted to my topic, music and morality, my fellow philosopher of music Peter Kivy makes a helpful tripartite distinction among ways in which music could be said to have moral force. The first is by embodying and conveying moral insight; Kivy labels that epistemic moral force. The second is by having a positive moral effect on behavior; Kivy labels that behavioral moral force. And the third is by impacting positively on character so as to make someone a better human being; Kivy…Read more
  •  1
    Book Reviews (review)
    Mind 104 (413): 197-202. 1995.
  •  64
    The real problem sustained: Reply to Wieand
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 61 (4). 2003.
  •  27
    Indication, abstraction, and individuation
    In Christy Mag Uidhir (ed.), Art & Abstract Objects, Oxford University Press. pp. 49. 2013.
  • Plaisanteries immorales
    Nouvelle Revue d'Esthétique 6 (2): 143-150. 2010.
    Résumé Pouvons-nous trouver une plaisanterie raciste ou sexiste à la fois drôle et moralement condamnable? Certains répondent « non », soit en tentant de montrer que l’immoralité disparaît dans le contexte de la plaisanterie, soit en soutenant que de telles plaisanteries ne sont pas réellement drôles ou ne devraient pas être trouvées telles. L’article soutient au contraire que oui! Et c’est de la mauvaise foi que de ne pas le reconnaître. La question est alors de savoir si leur immoralité nuit à…Read more
  •  1
    Aesthetic Properties, Evaluative Force, and Differences of Sensibility
    In Emily Brady & Jerrold Levinson (eds.), Aesthetic Concepts: Essays After Sibley, Oxford University Press. pp. 61--80. 2001.
  •  30
    Evaluating Musical Performance
    The Journal of Aesthetic Education 21 (1): 75. 1987.