• Review of John Dupre's Human Nature and the Limits of Science (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 18 (2): 357-362. 2002.
  •  31
    Introduction: What makes science possible
    with Stephen Stich and Michael Siegal
    In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Stich & Michael Siegal (eds.), The Cognitive Basis of Science, Cambridge University Press. 2002.
  •  10
    Some New Techniques for the Analysis Correlations of Point Distributions
    In R. J. Russell, N. Murphy & A. R. Peacocke (eds.), Chaos and Complexity, Vatican Observatory Publications. pp. 165. 1995.
  •  383
    Reductive explanation and the "explanatory gap"
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2): 153-174. 2004.
    Can phenomenal consciousness be given a reductive natural explanation? Exponents of an
  •  112
    Who is blind to blindsight?
    PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 7. 2001.
    This paper uses the explanation of blindsight generated by a two-systems theory of vision in order to set Siewert a dilemma. Either his blindsight examples are modelled on actual blindsight, in which case certain reductive theories of phenomenal consciousness will have no difficulty in accommodating them. Or they are intended to be purely imaginary, in which case they will have no force against a reductive naturalist
  • Consciousness and Concepts
    with Robert Kirk
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 66 23-59. 1992.
  •  190
    Valence and Value
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 97 (3): 658-680. 2017.
    Valence is a central component of all affective states, including pains, pleasures, emotions, moods, and feelings of desire or repulsion.This paper has two main goals. One is to suggest that enough is now known about the causes, consequences, and properties of valence to indicate that it forms a unitary natural-psychological kind, one that seemingly plays a fundamental role in motivating all kinds of intentional action. If this turns out to be true, then the correct characterization of the natur…Read more
  •  59
    Reductive Explanation and the "Explanatory Gap"
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2): 153-173. 2004.
    Can phenomenal consciousness be given a reductive natural explanation? Exponents of an ‘explanatory gap’ between physical, functional and intentional facts, on the one hand, and the facts of phenomenal consciousness, on the other, argue that there are reasons of principle why phenomenal consciousness cannot be reductively explained: Jackson, ; Levine,, ; McGinn ; Sturgeon, ; Chalmers,. Some of these writers claim that the existence of such a gap would warrant a belief in some form of ontological…Read more
  •  1
    Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory
    Philosophical Quarterly 52 (207): 265-268. 2002.
  •  29
    Phenomenal Consciousness
    Mind 110 (440): 1057-1062. 2001.
  •  12
    Natural Theories of Consciousness
    European Journal of Philosophy 6 (2): 203-222. 2002.
  • Norman Malcolm, "Nothing is Hidden" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 37 (48): 328. 1987.
  • Language, Thought and Consciousness
    Mind 106 (423): 593-596. 1997.
  •  75
    Implicit and explicit attitudes manifest themselves as distinct and partly dissociable behavioral dispositions. It is natural to think that these differences reflect differing underlying representations. The present article argues that this may be a mistake. Although non-verbal and verbal measures of attitudes often dissociate, this may be because the two types of outcome-measure are differentially impacted by other factors, not because they are tapping into distinct kinds of representation or d…Read more
  •  169
    Basic questions
    Mind and Language 33 (2): 130-147. 2018.
    This paper argues that a set of questioning attitudes are among the foundations of human and animal minds. While both verbal questioning and states of curiosity are generally explained in terms of metacognitive desires for knowledge or true belief, I argue that each is better explained by a prelinguistic sui generis type of mental attitude of questioning. I review a range of considerations in support of such a proposal and improve on previous characterizations of the nature of these attitudes. I…Read more
  •  404
    Why the question of animal consciousness might not matter very much
    Philosophical Psychology 18 (1): 83-102. 2005.
    According to higher-order thought accounts of phenomenal consciousness it is unlikely that many non-human animals undergo phenomenally conscious experiences. Many people believe that this result would have deep and far-reaching consequences. More specifically, they believe that the absence of phenomenal consciousness from the rest of the animal kingdom must mark a radical and theoretically significant divide between ourselves and other animals, with important implications for comparative psychol…Read more
  •  14
    The Cognitive Basis of Science (edited book)
    with Peter Carruthers, Stephen Stich, and Michael Siegal
    Cambridge University Press. 2002.
    The Cognitive Basis of Science concerns the question 'What makes science possible?' Specifically, what features of the human mind and of human culture and cognitive development permit and facilitate the conduct of science? The essays in this volume address these questions, which are inherently interdisciplinary, requiring co-operation between philosophers, psychologists, and others in the social and cognitive sciences. They concern the cognitive, social, and motivational underpinnings of scienti…Read more
  •  312
    Language in cognition
    In E. Margolis, R. Samuels & S. Stich (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Cognitive Science, Oxford University Press. 2008.
    In E. Margolis, R. Samuels, and S. Stich (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Cognitive Science. Oxford University Press, 2008.
  •  4
    Review (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (1). 1998.
  •  282
    Conscious experience versus conscious thought
    In Uriah Kriegel & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Consciousness and Self-Reference, Mit Press. 2006.
    Are there different constraints on theories of conscious experience as against theories of conscious propositional thought? Is what is problematic or puzzling about each of these phenomena of the same, or of different, types? And to what extent is it plausible to think that either or both conscious experience and conscious thought involve some sort of selfreference? In pursuing these questions I shall also explore the prospects for a defensible form of eliminativism concerning conscious thinking…Read more
  •  51
    Invertebrate concepts confront the generality constraint (and win)
    In Robert W. Lurz (ed.), The Philosophy of Animal Minds, Cambridge University Press. pp. 89--107. 2009.
  •  90
    Perceiving mental states
    Consciousness and Cognition 36 498-507. 2015.
  •  182
    Creative action in mind
    Philosophical Psychology 24 (4). 2011.
    The goal of this article is to display the attractiveness of a novel account of the place of creativity in the human mind. This is designed to supplement (and perhaps replace) the widespread assumption that creativity is thought-based, involving novel combinations of concepts to form creative thoughts, with the creativity of action being parasitic upon prior creative thinking. According to the proposed account, an additional (or perhaps alternative) locus of creativity lies in the assembly and a…Read more
  •  935
    We argue that Graziano and Kastner are mistaken to claim that neglect favors their self-directed social perception account of consciousness. For the latter should not predict that neglect would result from damage to mechanisms of social perception. Neglect is better explained in terms of damage to attentional mechanisms.
  •  229
    Human creativity: Its cognitive basis, its evolution, and its connections with childhood pretence
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 53 (2): 225-249. 2002.
    This paper defends two initial claims. First, it argues that essentially the same cognitive resources are shared by adult creative thinking and problem-solving, on the one hand, and by childhood pretend play, on the other—namely, capacities to generate and to reason with suppositions (or imagined possibilities). Second, it argues that the evolutionary function of childhood pretence is to practice and enhance adult forms of creativity. The paper goes on to show how these proposals can provide a s…Read more