• The Metaphysics of the Tractatus
    Philosophy 66 (255): 125-128. 1991.
  •  5
    Tractarian Semantics
    Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 183 (1): 105-105. 1989.
  •  8
    Book Review (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 18 (2): 351-385. 2002.
  •  8
    M. Hintikka and J. Hintikka, "Investigating Wittgenstein" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 38 (51): 244. 1988.
  •  2
    Unconsciously competing goals can collaborate or compromise as well as win or lose
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 37 (2): 139-140. 2014.
    This commentary offers a friendly extension of Huang & Bargh's (H&B's) account. Not only do active goals sometimes operate unconsciously to dominate or preempt others, but simultaneously active goals can also collaborate or compromise in shaping behavior. Because neither goal wins complete control of behavior, the result may be that each is only partly satisfied.
  • Review of John Dupre's Human Nature and the Limits of Science (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 18 (2): 357-362. 2002.
  •  7
    Introduction: What makes science possible
    with Stephen Stich and Michael Siegal
    In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Stich & Michael Siegal (eds.), The Cognitive Basis of Science, Cambridge University Press. 2002.
  •  2
    Some New Techniques for the Analysis Correlations of Point Distributions
    In R. J. Russell, N. Murphy & A. R. Peacocke (eds.), Chaos and Complexity, Vatican Observatory Publications. pp. 165. 1995.
  •  13
    Reductive explanation and the "explanatory gap"
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2): 153-174. 2004.
    Can phenomenal consciousness be given a reductive natural explanation? Exponents of an
  •  5
    Who is blind to blindsight?
    PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 7. 2001.
    This paper uses the explanation of blindsight generated by a two-systems theory of vision in order to set Siewert a dilemma. Either his blindsight examples are modelled on actual blindsight, in which case certain reductive theories of phenomenal consciousness will have no difficulty in accommodating them. Or they are intended to be purely imaginary, in which case they will have no force against a reductive naturalist
  • Consciousness and Concepts
    with Robert Kirk
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 66 23-59. 1992.
  • Argues that all of the behaviours that we share with non-human animals can, and should, be explained in terms of the first-order, non-phenomenal, contents of our experiences. So, although we do have phenomenally conscious experiences when we act, most of the time it is not by virtue of their being phenomenally conscious that they have their role in causing our actions. In consequence, the fact that my dispositional higher-order thought theory of phenomenal consciousness might withhold such consc…Read more
  •  199
    Valence and Value
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 97 (3): 658-680. 2017.
    Valence is a central component of all affective states, including pains, pleasures, emotions, moods, and feelings of desire or repulsion.This paper has two main goals. One is to suggest that enough is now known about the causes, consequences, and properties of valence to indicate that it forms a unitary natural-psychological kind, one that seemingly plays a fundamental role in motivating all kinds of intentional action. If this turns out to be true, then the correct characterization of the natur…Read more
  • Shows that even if the mental states of non-human animals lack phenomenal properties, as some accounts of mental-state consciousness imply, this need not prevent those states from being appropriate objects of sympathy and moral concern. Argues that the most basic form of mental harm lies in the existence of thwarted agency, or thwarted desire, rather than in anything phenomenological. So, provided that animals are capable of desire, and of sometimes believing, of the objects desired, that they h…Read more
  • Exponents of an ‘explanatory gap’ between physical, functional, and intentional facts, on the one hand, and the facts of phenomenal consciousness, on the other, argue that there are reasons of principle why phenomenal consciousness cannot be reductively explained. Some writers claim that the existence of such a gap warrants a belief in some form of ontological dualism, whereas others argue that no such entailment holds. In the other main camp, there are people who argue that a reductive explanat…Read more
  •  61
    Reductive Explanation and the 'Explanatory Gap'
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2): 153-173. 2004.
    Can phenomenal consciousness be given a reductive natural explanation? Exponents of an ‘explanatory gap’ between physical, functional and intentional facts, on the one hand, and the facts of phenomenal consciousness, on the other, argue that there are reasons of principle why phenomenal consciousness cannot be reductively explained: Jackson (1982), (1986); Levine (1983), (1993), (2001); McGinn (1991); Sturgeon (1994), (2000); Chalmers (1996), (1999). Some of these writers claim that the existenc…Read more
  •  1
    Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory
    Philosophical Quarterly 52 (207): 265-268. 2002.
  • Argues for the need to recognise higher-order perceptual experiences and briefly argues for the superiority of the author’s own dispositional HOT version of higher-order perception theory. But its main focus is on purely recognitional concepts of experience. There is an emerging consensus amongst naturalistically minded philosophers that the existence of such concepts is the key to blocking the zombie-style arguments of both dualist mysterians like Chalmers and physicalist mysterians like McGinn…Read more
  • Argues that belief/desire psychology – and with it a form of first-order access-consciousness – are very widely distributed in the animal kingdom, being shared even by navigating insects. Although the main topic of this chapter is not mental-state consciousness, it serves both to underscore the argument of the previous chapter, and to emphasise how wide is the phylogenetic distance separating mentality per se from phenomenally conscious mentality. On some views, these things are intimately conne…Read more
  •  31
    Phenomenal Consciousness
    Mind 110 (440): 1057-1062. 2001.
  •  12
    Natural Theories of Consciousness
    European Journal of Philosophy 6 (2): 203-222. 2002.
  • Works its way through a variety of different accounts of phenomenal consciousness, looking at the strengths and weaknesses of each. At the heart of the chapter is an extended critical examination of first-order representational theories, of the sort espoused by Dretske and Tye, arguing that they are inferior to higher-order representational accounts. Acknowledges as a problem for HOR theories that they might withhold phenomenal consciousness from most other species of animal, but claims that thi…Read more
  • Norman Malcolm, "Nothing is Hidden" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 37 (48): 328. 1987.
  • Language, Thought and Consciousness
    Mind 106 (423): 593-596. 1997.
  •  75
    Implicit and explicit attitudes manifest themselves as distinct and partly dissociable behavioral dispositions. It is natural to think that these differences reflect differing underlying representations. The present article argues that this may be a mistake. Although non-verbal and verbal measures of attitudes often dissociate, this may be because the two types of outcome-measure are differentially impacted by other factors, not because they are tapping into distinct kinds of representation or d…Read more
  • Presents and develops what the author takes to be the main argument, both against the most plausible version of first-order representationalist theory of phenomenal consciousness, and in support of his own higher-order perception/dual-content account. The primary goal of the chapter is to lay out the case for saying that dual-content theory provides us with a successful reductive explanation of the various puzzling features of phenomenal consciousness. Also takes up the question whether a first-…Read more