•  14
    Unconsciously competing goals can collaborate or compromise as well as win or lose
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 37 (2): 139-140. 2014.
    This commentary offers a friendly extension of Huang & Bargh's (H&B's) account. Not only do active goals sometimes operate unconsciously to dominate or preempt others, but simultaneously active goals can also collaborate or compromise in shaping behavior. Because neither goal wins complete control of behavior, the result may be that each is only partly satisfied.
  • Review of John Dupre's Human Nature and the Limits of Science (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 18 (2): 357-362. 2002.
  •  31
    Introduction: What makes science possible
    with Stephen Stich and Michael Siegal
    In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Stich & Michael Siegal (eds.), The Cognitive Basis of Science, Cambridge University Press. 2002.
  •  10
    Some New Techniques for the Analysis Correlations of Point Distributions
    In R. J. Russell, N. Murphy & A. R. Peacocke (eds.), Chaos and Complexity, Vatican Observatory Publications. pp. 165. 1995.
  •  385
    Reductive explanation and the "explanatory gap"
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2): 153-174. 2004.
    Can phenomenal consciousness be given a reductive natural explanation? Exponents of an
  •  112
    Who is blind to blindsight?
    PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 7. 2001.
    This paper uses the explanation of blindsight generated by a two-systems theory of vision in order to set Siewert a dilemma. Either his blindsight examples are modelled on actual blindsight, in which case certain reductive theories of phenomenal consciousness will have no difficulty in accommodating them. Or they are intended to be purely imaginary, in which case they will have no force against a reductive naturalist
  • Consciousness and Concepts
    with Robert Kirk
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 66 23-59. 1992.
  •  199
    Valence and Value
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 97 (3): 658-680. 2017.
    Valence is a central component of all affective states, including pains, pleasures, emotions, moods, and feelings of desire or repulsion.This paper has two main goals. One is to suggest that enough is now known about the causes, consequences, and properties of valence to indicate that it forms a unitary natural-psychological kind, one that seemingly plays a fundamental role in motivating all kinds of intentional action. If this turns out to be true, then the correct characterization of the natur…Read more
  •  61
    Reductive Explanation and the 'Explanatory Gap'
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2): 153-173. 2004.
    Can phenomenal consciousness be given a reductive natural explanation? Exponents of an ‘explanatory gap’ between physical, functional and intentional facts, on the one hand, and the facts of phenomenal consciousness, on the other, argue that there are reasons of principle why phenomenal consciousness cannot be reductively explained: Jackson (1982), (1986); Levine (1983), (1993), (2001); McGinn (1991); Sturgeon (1994), (2000); Chalmers (1996), (1999). Some of these writers claim that the existenc…Read more
  •  1
    Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory
    Philosophical Quarterly 52 (207): 265-268. 2002.
  •  31
    Phenomenal Consciousness
    Mind 110 (440): 1057-1062. 2001.
  • Norman Malcolm, "Nothing is Hidden" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 37 (48): 328. 1987.
  •  12
    Natural Theories of Consciousness
    European Journal of Philosophy 6 (2): 203-222. 2002.
  • Language, Thought and Consciousness
    Mind 106 (423): 593-596. 1997.
  •  75
    Implicit and explicit attitudes manifest themselves as distinct and partly dissociable behavioral dispositions. It is natural to think that these differences reflect differing underlying representations. The present article argues that this may be a mistake. Although non-verbal and verbal measures of attitudes often dissociate, this may be because the two types of outcome-measure are differentially impacted by other factors, not because they are tapping into distinct kinds of representation or d…Read more
  •  180
    Basic questions
    Mind and Language 33 (2): 130-147. 2018.
    This paper argues that a set of questioning attitudes are among the foundations of human and animal minds. While both verbal questioning and states of curiosity are generally explained in terms of metacognitive desires for knowledge or true belief, I argue that each is better explained by a prelinguistic sui generis type of mental attitude of questioning. I review a range of considerations in support of such a proposal and improve on previous characterizations of the nature of these attitudes. I…Read more
  •  99
    Practical reasoning in a modular mind
    Mind and Language 19 (3): 259-278. 2004.
      This paper starts from an assumption defended in the author's previous work. This is that distinctivelyhuman flexible and creative theoretical thinking can be explained in terms of the interactions of a variety of modular systems, with the addition of just a few amodular components and dispositions. On the basis of that assumption it is argued that distinctively human practical reasoning, too, can be understood in modular terms. The upshot is that there is nothing in the human psyche that requ…Read more
  •  151
    Consciousness: Explaining the phenomena
    In D. Walsh (ed.), Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, Cambridge University Press. pp. 61-85. 2001.
    Can phenomenal consciousness be given a reductive natural explanation? Many people argue not. They claim that there is an
  •  269
    This book is a comprehensive development and defense of one of the guiding assumptions of evolutionary psychology: that the human mind is composed of a large number of semi-independent modules. The Architecture of the Mind has three main goals. One is to argue for massive mental modularity. Another is to answer a 'How possibly?' challenge to any such approach. The first part of the book lays out the positive case supporting massive modularity. It also outlines how the thesis should best be devel…Read more
  •  147
    Language and Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes (edited book)
    with Jill Boucher
    Cambridge University Press. 1998.
    What is the place of language in human cognition? Do we sometimes think in natural language? Or is language for purposes of interpersonal communication only? Although these questions have been much debated in the past, they have almost dropped from sight in recent decades amongst those interested in the cognitive sciences. Language and Thought is intended to persuade such people to think again. It brings together essays by a distinguished interdisciplinary team of philosophers and psychologists,…Read more
  •  13
    Wittgenstein on Meaning
    Philosophical Books 27 (1): 36-38. 1986.
  •  1
    Book Reviews (review)
    Mind 97 (388): 640-642. 1988.
  •  28
    Introducing Persons
    Philosophical Quarterly 38 (150): 123. 1988.
    This is an elegant and clear tour through many of the issues in philosophy of mind that have occupied philosophers of this century. The topics covered include the problem of other minds, arguments for and against the existence of the soul, a discussion of the bundle theory of the mind, behaviorism, functionalism, mind/brain identity, the argument against the possibility of private language, personal identity and the possibility of after-life, and the question of whether animals and computers can…Read more
  •  256
    Sympathy and subjectivity
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 (4): 465-82. 1999.
    This paper shows that even if the mental states of non-human animals lack phenomenological properties, as some accounts of mental-state consciousness imply, this need not prevent those states from being appropriate objects of sympathy and moral concern. The paper argues that the most basic form of mental (as opposed to biological) harm lies in the existence of thwarted agency, or thwarted desire, rather than in anything phenomenological
  •  360
    ""Banishing" I" and" we" from accounts of metacognition
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (2): 148. 2009.
    SHORT ABSTRACT: A number of accounts of the relationship between third-person mindreading and first-person metacognition are compared and evaluated. While three of these accounts endorse the existence of introspection for propositional attitudes, the fourth (defended here) claims that our knowledge of our own attitudes results from turning our mindreading capacities upon ourselves. The different types of theory are developed and evaluated, and multiple lines of evidence are reviewed, including e…Read more
  •  226
    Theories of Theories of Mind (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 1996.
    Theories of Theories of Mind brings together contributions by a distinguished international team of philosophers, psychologists, and primatologists, who between them address such questions as: what is it to understand the thoughts, feelings, and intentions of other people? How does such an understanding develop in the normal child? Why, unusually, does it fail to develop? And is any such mentalistic understanding shared by members of other species? The volume's four parts together offer a state …Read more