•  8
    M. Hintikka and J. Hintikka, "Investigating Wittgenstein" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 38 (51): 244. 1988.
  •  14
    Unconsciously competing goals can collaborate or compromise as well as win or lose
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 37 (2): 139-140. 2014.
    This commentary offers a friendly extension of Huang & Bargh's (H&B's) account. Not only do active goals sometimes operate unconsciously to dominate or preempt others, but simultaneously active goals can also collaborate or compromise in shaping behavior. Because neither goal wins complete control of behavior, the result may be that each is only partly satisfied.
  • Review of John Dupre's Human Nature and the Limits of Science (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 18 (2): 357-362. 2002.
  •  31
    Introduction: What makes science possible
    with Stephen Stich and Michael Siegal
    In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Stich & Michael Siegal (eds.), The Cognitive Basis of Science, Cambridge University Press. 2002.
  •  10
    Some New Techniques for the Analysis Correlations of Point Distributions
    In R. J. Russell, N. Murphy & A. R. Peacocke (eds.), Chaos and Complexity, Vatican Observatory Publications. pp. 165. 1995.
  •  13
    Reductive explanation and the "explanatory gap"
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2): 153-174. 2004.
    Can phenomenal consciousness be given a reductive natural explanation? Exponents of an
  •  5
    Who is blind to blindsight?
    PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 7. 2001.
    This paper uses the explanation of blindsight generated by a two-systems theory of vision in order to set Siewert a dilemma. Either his blindsight examples are modelled on actual blindsight, in which case certain reductive theories of phenomenal consciousness will have no difficulty in accommodating them. Or they are intended to be purely imaginary, in which case they will have no force against a reductive naturalist
  • Consciousness and Concepts
    with Robert Kirk
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 66 23-59. 1992.
  •  199
    Valence and Value
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 97 (3): 658-680. 2017.
    Valence is a central component of all affective states, including pains, pleasures, emotions, moods, and feelings of desire or repulsion.This paper has two main goals. One is to suggest that enough is now known about the causes, consequences, and properties of valence to indicate that it forms a unitary natural-psychological kind, one that seemingly plays a fundamental role in motivating all kinds of intentional action. If this turns out to be true, then the correct characterization of the natur…Read more
  •  61
    Reductive Explanation and the 'Explanatory Gap'
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2): 153-173. 2004.
    Can phenomenal consciousness be given a reductive natural explanation? Exponents of an ‘explanatory gap’ between physical, functional and intentional facts, on the one hand, and the facts of phenomenal consciousness, on the other, argue that there are reasons of principle why phenomenal consciousness cannot be reductively explained: Jackson (1982), (1986); Levine (1983), (1993), (2001); McGinn (1991); Sturgeon (1994), (2000); Chalmers (1996), (1999). Some of these writers claim that the existenc…Read more
  •  1
    Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory
    Philosophical Quarterly 52 (207): 265-268. 2002.
  •  31
    Phenomenal Consciousness
    Mind 110 (440): 1057-1062. 2001.
  • Norman Malcolm, "Nothing is Hidden" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 37 (48): 328. 1987.
  •  12
    Natural Theories of Consciousness
    European Journal of Philosophy 6 (2): 203-222. 2002.
  • Language, Thought and Consciousness
    Mind 106 (423): 593-596. 1997.
  •  75
    Implicit and explicit attitudes manifest themselves as distinct and partly dissociable behavioral dispositions. It is natural to think that these differences reflect differing underlying representations. The present article argues that this may be a mistake. Although non-verbal and verbal measures of attitudes often dissociate, this may be because the two types of outcome-measure are differentially impacted by other factors, not because they are tapping into distinct kinds of representation or d…Read more
  •  180
    Basic questions
    Mind and Language 33 (2): 130-147. 2018.
    This paper argues that a set of questioning attitudes are among the foundations of human and animal minds. While both verbal questioning and states of curiosity are generally explained in terms of metacognitive desires for knowledge or true belief, I argue that each is better explained by a prelinguistic sui generis type of mental attitude of questioning. I review a range of considerations in support of such a proposal and improve on previous characterizations of the nature of these attitudes. I…Read more
  •  9
    Monitoring without metacognition
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (3): 342-343. 2003.
    Smith et al. present us with a false dichotomy in explaining their uncertainty data: Either the animals' responses are “under the associative control of stimulus cues,” or the animals must be responding “under the metacognitive control of uncertainty cues.” There is a third alternative to consider: one that is genuinely cognitive, neither associative nor stimulus driven, but purely first-order in character. On this alternative the metacognitive reports of humans in these situations reflect state…Read more
  •  12
    Action-Awareness and the Active Mind
    Philosophical Papers 38 (2): 133-156. 2009.
    In a pair of recent papers and his new book, Christopher Peacocke (2007, 2008a, 2008b) takes up and defends the claim that our awareness of our own actions is immediate and not perceptually based, and extends it into the domain of mental action.1 He aims to provide an account of action-awareness that will generalize to explain how we have immediate awareness of our own judgments, decisions, imaginings, and so forth. These claims form an important component in a much larger philosophical edifice,…Read more
  •  1
    Replies to critics: Explaining subjectivity
    PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 6. 2000.
    This article replies to the main objections raised by the commentators on Carruthers . It discusses the question of what evidence is relevant to the assessment of dispositional higher-order thought theory; it explains how the actual properties of phenomenal consciousness can be dispositionally constituted; it discusses the case of pains and other bodily sensations in non-human animals and young children; it sketches the case for preferring higher-order to first-order theories of phenomenal consc…Read more
  •  29
    Tractarian Semantics.The Metaphysics of the Tractatus
    with Edwin B. Allaire
    Philosophical Review 106 (3): 444. 1997.
    Tractarian Semantics is full of claims that clash with the Tractatus, not to mention each other. There seems to be a method to it though. The book.
  • Review of Recreative Minds (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. forthcoming.
  •  7
    Distinctively human thinking: Modular precursors and components
    In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Laurence & Stephen P. Stich (eds.), The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents, Oxford University Press Usa. pp. 69--88. 2005.
  •  117
    The Evolution of Self-Knowledge
    Philosophical Topics 40 (2): 13-37. 2012.
    Humans have the capacity for awareness of many aspects of their own mental lives—their own experiences, feelings, judgments, desires, and decisions. We can often know what it is that we see, hear, feel, judge, want, or decide. This article examines the evolutionary origins of this form of self-knowledge. Two alternatives are contrasted and compared with the available evidence. One is first-person based: self-knowledge is an adaptation designed initially for metacognitive monitoring and control. …Read more