•  183
    Why the quantum?
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (2): 241-266. 2004.
  •  112
    Quantum computation and pseudotelepathic games
    Philosophy of Science 75 (4): 458-472. 2008.
    A quantum algorithm succeeds not because the superposition principle allows ‘the computation of all values of a function at once’ via ‘quantum parallelism’, but rather because the structure of a quantum state space allows new sorts of correlations associated with entanglement, with new possibilities for information‐processing transformations between correlations, that are not possible in a classical state space. I illustrate this with an elementary example of a problem for which a quantum algori…Read more
  •  114
    The Quantum Bit Commitment Theorem
    Foundations of Physics 31 (5): 735-756. 2001.
    Unconditionally secure two-party bit commitment based solely on the principles of quantum mechanics (without exploiting special relativistic signalling constraints, or principles of general relativity or thermodynamics) has been shown to be impossible, but the claim is repeatedly challenged. The quantum bit commitment theorem is reviewed here and the central conceptual point, that an “Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen” attack or cheating strategy can always be applied, is clarified. The question of whethe…Read more
  •  89
    On Bohr's response to EPR: A quantum logical analysis (review)
    Foundations of Physics 19 (7): 793-805. 1989.
    Bohr's complementarity interpretation is represented as the relativization of the quantum mechanical description of a system to the maximal Boolean subalgebra (in the non-Boolean logical structure of the system) selected by a classically described experimental arrangement. Only propositions in this subalgebra have determinate truth values. The concept of a minimal revision of a Boolean subalgebra by a measurement is defined, and it is shown that the nonmaximal measurement of spin on one subsyste…Read more
  •  239
    Two dogmas about quantum mechanics
    with Itamar Pitowsky
    In Simon Saunders, Jonathan Barrett, Adrian Kent & David Wallace (eds.), Many Worlds?: Everett, Quantum Theory & Reality, Oxford University Press. 2007.
    We argue that the intractable part of the measurement problem -- the 'big' measurement problem -- is a pseudo-problem that depends for its legitimacy on the acceptance of two dogmas. The first dogma is John Bell's assertion that measurement should never be introduced as a primitive process in a fundamental mechanical theory like classical or quantum mechanics, but should always be open to a complete analysis, in principle, of how the individual outcomes come about dynamically. The second dogma i…Read more
  • Interpreting the Quantum World
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (4): 637-641. 1998.
  •  21
    Introduction
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (2): 143-149. 2004.
  •  133
    Revised Proof of the Uniqueness Theorem for ‘No Collapse’ Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics
    with Rob Clifton and Sheldon Goldstein
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 31 (1): 95-98. 2000.
    We show that the Bub-Clifton uniqueness theorem (1996) for 'no collapse' interpretations of quantum mechanics can be proved without the 'weak separability' assumption.
  •  69
    From Micro to Macro: A Solution to the Measurement Problem of Quantum Mechanics
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988. 1988.
    Philosophical debate on the measurement problem of quantum mechanics has, for the most part, been confined to the non-relativistic version of the theory. Quantizing quantum field theory, or making quantum mechanics relativistic, yields a conceptual framework capable of dealing with the creation and annihilation of an indefinite number of particles in interaction with fields, i.e. quantum systems with an infinite number of degrees of freedom. I show that a solution to the standard measurement pro…Read more
  •  60
    Quantum logic, conditional probability, and interference
    Philosophy of Science 49 (3): 402-421. 1982.
    Friedman and Putnam have argued (Friedman and Putnam 1978) that the quantum logical interpretation of quantum mechanics gives us an explanation of interference that the Copenhagen interpretation cannot supply without invoking an additional ad hoc principle, the projection postulate. I show that it is possible to define a notion of equivalence of experimental arrangements relative to a pure state φ , or (correspondingly) equivalence of Boolean subalgebras in the partial Boolean algebra of project…Read more
  •  164
    Von Neumann’s ‘No Hidden Variables’ Proof: A Re-Appraisal (review)
    Foundations of Physics 40 (9-10): 1333-1340. 2010.
    Since the analysis by John Bell in 1965, the consensus in the literature is that von Neumann’s ‘no hidden variables’ proof fails to exclude any significant class of hidden variables. Bell raised the question whether it could be shown that any hidden variable theory would have to be nonlocal, and in this sense ‘like Bohm’s theory.’ His seminal result provides a positive answer to the question. I argue that Bell’s analysis misconstrues von Neumann’s argument. What von Neumann proved was the imposs…Read more
  •  32
    On the structure of quantal proposition systems
    Foundations of Physics 24 (9): 1261-1279. 1994.
    I define sublaltices of quantum propositions that can be taken as having determinate (but perhaps unknown) truth values for a given quantum state, in the sense that sufficiently many two-valued maps satisfying a Boolean homomorphism condition exist on each determinate sublattice to generate a Kolmogorov probability space for the probabilities defined by the slate. I show that these sublattices are maximal, subject to certain constraints, from which it follows easily that they are unique. I discu…Read more
  •  167
    The problem of properties in quantum mechanics
    Topoi 10 (1): 27-34. 1991.
    The properties of classical and quantum systems are characterized by different algebraic structures. We know that the properties of a quantum mechanical system form a partial Boolean algebra not embeddable into a Boolean algebra, and so cannot all be co-determinate. We also know that maximal Boolean subalgebras of properties can be (separately) co-determinate. Are there larger subsets of properties that can be co-determinate without contradiction? Following an analysis of Bohrs response to the E…Read more
  •  3
    Nancy Cartwright, How The Laws of Physics Lie (review)
    Philosophy in Review 5 (3): 104-107. 1985.
  •  16
    A quantum key distribution scheme whose security depends on the features of pre- and post-selected quantum states is described.
  •  15
    Incompleteness, Nonlocality, and Realism (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 22 (3): 140-141. 1990.
  •  120
    Correlations, Contextuality and Quantum Logic
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 42 (3): 483-499. 2013.
    Quantum theory is a probabilistic theory that embodies notoriously striking correlations, stronger than any that classical theories allow but not as strong as those of hypothetical ‘super-quantum’ theories. This raises the question ‘Why the quantum?’—whether there is a handful of principles that account for the character of quantum probability. We ask what quantum-logical notions correspond to this investigation. This project isn’t meant to compete with the many beautiful results that informatio…Read more
  •  106
    Quantum probabilities as degrees of belief
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (2): 232-254. 2007.
  •  22
    Why the Tsirelson bound?
    In Yemima Ben-Menahem & Meir Hemmo (eds.), Probability in Physics, Springer. pp. 167--185. 2012.
  •  115
    A uniqueness theorem for ‘no collapse’ interpretations of quantum mechanics
    with Rob Clifton
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 27 (2): 181-219. 1996.
    We prove a uniqueness theorem showing that, subject to certain natural constraints, all 'no collapse' interpretations of quantum mechanics can be uniquely characterized and reduced to the choice of a particular preferred observable as determine (definite, sharp). We show how certain versions of the modal interpretation, Bohm's 'causal' interpretation, Bohr's complementarity interpretation, and the orthodox (Dirac-von Neumann) interpretation without the projection postulate can be recovered from …Read more
  •  70
    On Bohr's response to EPR: II (review)
    Foundations of Physics 20 (8): 929-941. 1990.
    In my reconstruction of Bohr's reply to the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen argument, I pointed out that Bohr showed explicitly, within the framework of the complementarity interpretation, how a locally maximal measurement on a subsystem S2 of a composite system S1+S2, consisting of two spatially separated subsystems, can make determinate both a locally maximal Boolean subalgebra for S2 and a locally maximal Boolean subalgebra for S1. As it stands, this response is open to an objection. In this note, I …Read more
  • The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics
    Erkenntnis 12 (3): 399-402. 1978.
  •  30
    Measurement and “beables” in quantum mechanics
    Foundations of Physics 21 (1): 25-42. 1991.
    It is argued that the measurement problem reduces to the problem of modeling quasi-classical systems in a modified quantum mechanics with superselection rules. A measurement theorem is proved, demonstrating, on the basis of a principle for selecting the quantities of a system that are determinate (i.e., have values) in a given state, that after a suitable interaction between a systemS and a quasi-classical systemM, essentially only the quantity measured in the interaction and the indicator quant…Read more
  •  8
    Review: The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (2). 1989.
  •  189
    Indeterminacy and entanglement: the challenge of quantum mechanics
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (4): 597-615. 2000.
    I explore the nature of the problem generated by the transition from classical to quantum mechanics, and I survey some of the different responses to this problem. I show briefly how recent work on quantum information over the past ten years has led to a shift of focus, in which the puzzling features of quantum mechanics are seen as a resource to be developed rather than a problem to be solved
  •  15
    Book Review:Niels Bohr's Philosophy of Physics Dugald Murdoch (review)
    Philosophy of Science 57 (2): 344-. 1990.