•  1
    What’s the deal with the really, really, weird-acting stuff that everything is made of? Can we ever take in our everyday world the same way again if we fully understand the nature of the quantum world? With Jeffrey Bub , Tim Maudlin , and Drew Arrowood
  •  45
    How to solve the measurement problem of quantum mechanics
    Foundations of Physics 18 (7): 701-722. 1988.
    A solution to the measurement problem of quantum mechanics is proposed within the framework of an intepretation according to which only quantum systems with an infinite number of degrees of freedom have determinate properties, i.e., determinate values for (some) observables of the theory. The important feature of the infinite case is the existence of many inequivalent irreducible Hilbert space representations of the algebra of observables, which leads, in effect, to a restriction on the superpos…Read more
  •  41
    Postscript to the Logic of Scientific Discovery (review)
    with Itamar Pitowsky
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (3): 539-552. 1985.
  •  26
    Von Neumann’s Theory of Quantum Measurement
    Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 8 63-74. 2001.
    In a series of lectures written around 1952, Schrödinger refers to von Neumann’s account of measurement in quantum mechanics as follows:I said quantum physicists bother very little about accounting, according to the accepted law, for the supposed change of the wave-function by measurement. I know of only one attempt in this direction, to which Dr. Balazs recently directed my attention. You find it in John von Neumann’s well-known book. With great acuity he constructs one analytical example. It d…Read more
  •  2
    94 obituary
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 17 (1). 2003.
  •  108
    Schütte's tautology and the Kochen-Specker theorem
    Foundations of Physics 26 (6): 787-806. 1996.
    I present a new 33-ray proof of the Kochen and Specker “no-go” hidden variable theorem in ℋ3, based on a classical tautology that corresponds to a contingent quantum proposition in ℋ3 proposed by Kurt Schütte in an unpublished letter to Specker in 1965. 1 discuss the relation of this proof to a 31-ray proof by Conway and Kochen, and to a 33-ray proof by Peres
  •  53
    Itamar Pitowsky 1950–2010
    with Williams Demopoulos
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 41 (2): 85-. 2010.
  • Rob Clifton (1964-2002)
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 17 (1): 93-94. 2003.
  •  58
    On local realism and commutativity
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (4): 863-878. 2007.
  •  16
    Introduction
    with A. C.
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 34 (3): 339-341. 2003.
  •  110
    Epr
    Foundations of Physics 22 (3): 313-332. 1992.
    We present an exegesis of the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen argument for the incompleteness of quantum mechanics, and defend it against the critique in Fine. (1) We contend,contra Fine, that it compares favorably with an argument reconstructed by him from a letter by Einstein to Schrödinger; and also with one given by Einstein in a letter to Popper. All three arguments turn on a dubious assumption of “separability,” which accords separate elements of reality to space-like separated systems. We discuss…Read more
  •  8
    Critical notice (review)
    with Itamar Pitowsky
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (3): 539-552. 1985.
  •  106
    J. S. Bell's argument that only “nonlocal” hidden variable theories can reproduce the quantum statistical correlations of the singlet spin state in the case of two separated spin-1/2 particles is examined in terms of Wigner's formulation. It is shown that a similar argument applies to a single spin-1/2 particle, and that the exclusion of hidden variables depends on an obviously untenable assumption concerning conditional probabilities. The problem of completeness is discussed briefly, and the gr…Read more
  •  59
    Under the spell of Bohr (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24 (1): 78-90. 1973.
  •  102
    Miller's paradox of information
    with Michael Radner
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 19 (1): 63-67. 1968.
  •  244
    Testing models of cognition through the analysis of brain-damaged patients
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (3): 837-55. 1994.
    The aim of cognitive neuropsychology is to articulate the functional architecture underlying normal cognition, on the basis of congnitive performance data involving brain-damaged subjects. Throughout the history of the subject, questions have been raised as to whether the methods of neuropsychology are adequate to its goals. The question has been reopened by Glymour [1994], who formulates a discovery problem for cognitive neuropsychology, in the sense of formal learning theory, concerning the ex…Read more
  •  6
    Review: Under the Spell of Bohr (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24 (1). 1973.
  •  102
    I consider to what extent the phenomenon of interference precludes the possibility of attributing simultaneously determinate values to noncommuting observables, and I show that, while all observables can in principle be taken as simultaneously determinate, it suffices to take a suitable privileged observable as determinate to solve the measurement problem.
  •  38
    Quantum mechanics without the projection postulate
    Foundations of Physics 22 (5): 737-754. 1992.
    I show that the quantum state ω can be interpreted as defining a probability measure on a subalgebra of the algebra of projection operators that is not fixed (as in classical statistical mechanics) but changes with ω and appropriate boundary conditions, hence with the dynamics of the theory. This subalgebra, while not embeddable into a Boolean algebra, will always admit two-valued homomorphisms, which correspond to the different possible ways in which a set of “determinate” quantities (selected …Read more
  •  26
    John von Neumann and the Foundations of Quantum Physics
    with Miklós Rédei, Michael Stöltzner, Walter Thirring, and Ulrich Majer
    Springer Verlag. 2013.
    John von Neumann (1903-1957) was undoubtedly one of the scientific geniuses of the 20th century. The main fields to which he contributed include various disciplines of pure and applied mathematics, mathematical and theoretical physics, logic, theoretical computer science, and computer architecture. Von Neumann was also actively involved in politics and science management and he had a major impact on US government decisions during, and especially after, the Second World War. There exist several p…Read more
  •  108
    Hidden Variables and the Copenhagen Interpretation—A Reconciliation1
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 19 (3): 185-210. 1968.
  •  112
    Quantum computation and pseudotelepathic games
    Philosophy of Science 75 (4): 458-472. 2008.
    A quantum algorithm succeeds not because the superposition principle allows ‘the computation of all values of a function at once’ via ‘quantum parallelism’, but rather because the structure of a quantum state space allows new sorts of correlations associated with entanglement, with new possibilities for information‐processing transformations between correlations, that are not possible in a classical state space. I illustrate this with an elementary example of a problem for which a quantum algori…Read more
  •  183
    Why the quantum?
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (2): 241-266. 2004.
  •  89
    On Bohr's response to EPR: A quantum logical analysis (review)
    Foundations of Physics 19 (7): 793-805. 1989.
    Bohr's complementarity interpretation is represented as the relativization of the quantum mechanical description of a system to the maximal Boolean subalgebra (in the non-Boolean logical structure of the system) selected by a classically described experimental arrangement. Only propositions in this subalgebra have determinate truth values. The concept of a minimal revision of a Boolean subalgebra by a measurement is defined, and it is shown that the nonmaximal measurement of spin on one subsyste…Read more
  •  114
    The Quantum Bit Commitment Theorem
    Foundations of Physics 31 (5): 735-756. 2001.
    Unconditionally secure two-party bit commitment based solely on the principles of quantum mechanics (without exploiting special relativistic signalling constraints, or principles of general relativity or thermodynamics) has been shown to be impossible, but the claim is repeatedly challenged. The quantum bit commitment theorem is reviewed here and the central conceptual point, that an “Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen” attack or cheating strategy can always be applied, is clarified. The question of whethe…Read more
  •  238
    Two dogmas about quantum mechanics
    with Itamar Pitowsky
    In Simon Saunders, Jonathan Barrett, Adrian Kent & David Wallace (eds.), Many Worlds?: Everett, Quantum Theory & Reality, Oxford University Press. 2007.
    We argue that the intractable part of the measurement problem -- the 'big' measurement problem -- is a pseudo-problem that depends for its legitimacy on the acceptance of two dogmas. The first dogma is John Bell's assertion that measurement should never be introduced as a primitive process in a fundamental mechanical theory like classical or quantum mechanics, but should always be open to a complete analysis, in principle, of how the individual outcomes come about dynamically. The second dogma i…Read more
  • Interpreting the Quantum World
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (4): 637-641. 1998.
  •  133
    Revised Proof of the Uniqueness Theorem for ‘No Collapse’ Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics
    with Rob Clifton and Sheldon Goldstein
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 31 (1): 95-98. 2000.
    We show that the Bub-Clifton uniqueness theorem (1996) for 'no collapse' interpretations of quantum mechanics can be proved without the 'weak separability' assumption.