•  38
    Quantum mechanics without the projection postulate
    Foundations of Physics 22 (5): 737-754. 1992.
    I show that the quantum state ω can be interpreted as defining a probability measure on a subalgebra of the algebra of projection operators that is not fixed (as in classical statistical mechanics) but changes with ω and appropriate boundary conditions, hence with the dynamics of the theory. This subalgebra, while not embeddable into a Boolean algebra, will always admit two-valued homomorphisms, which correspond to the different possible ways in which a set of “determinate” quantities (selected …Read more
  •  183
    Why the quantum?
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (2): 241-266. 2004.
  •  112
    Quantum computation and pseudotelepathic games
    Philosophy of Science 75 (4): 458-472. 2008.
    A quantum algorithm succeeds not because the superposition principle allows ‘the computation of all values of a function at once’ via ‘quantum parallelism’, but rather because the structure of a quantum state space allows new sorts of correlations associated with entanglement, with new possibilities for information‐processing transformations between correlations, that are not possible in a classical state space. I illustrate this with an elementary example of a problem for which a quantum algori…Read more
  •  89
    On Bohr's response to EPR: A quantum logical analysis (review)
    Foundations of Physics 19 (7): 793-805. 1989.
    Bohr's complementarity interpretation is represented as the relativization of the quantum mechanical description of a system to the maximal Boolean subalgebra (in the non-Boolean logical structure of the system) selected by a classically described experimental arrangement. Only propositions in this subalgebra have determinate truth values. The concept of a minimal revision of a Boolean subalgebra by a measurement is defined, and it is shown that the nonmaximal measurement of spin on one subsyste…Read more
  •  114
    The Quantum Bit Commitment Theorem
    Foundations of Physics 31 (5): 735-756. 2001.
    Unconditionally secure two-party bit commitment based solely on the principles of quantum mechanics (without exploiting special relativistic signalling constraints, or principles of general relativity or thermodynamics) has been shown to be impossible, but the claim is repeatedly challenged. The quantum bit commitment theorem is reviewed here and the central conceptual point, that an “Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen” attack or cheating strategy can always be applied, is clarified. The question of whethe…Read more
  • Interpreting the Quantum World
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (4): 637-641. 1998.
  •  237
    Two dogmas about quantum mechanics
    with Itamar Pitowsky
    In Simon Saunders, Jonathan Barrett, Adrian Kent & David Wallace (eds.), Many Worlds?: Everett, Quantum Theory & Reality, Oxford University Press. 2007.
    We argue that the intractable part of the measurement problem -- the 'big' measurement problem -- is a pseudo-problem that depends for its legitimacy on the acceptance of two dogmas. The first dogma is John Bell's assertion that measurement should never be introduced as a primitive process in a fundamental mechanical theory like classical or quantum mechanics, but should always be open to a complete analysis, in principle, of how the individual outcomes come about dynamically. The second dogma i…Read more
  •  21
    Introduction
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (2): 143-149. 2004.
  •  133
    Revised Proof of the Uniqueness Theorem for ‘No Collapse’ Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics
    with Rob Clifton and Sheldon Goldstein
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 31 (1): 95-98. 2000.
    We show that the Bub-Clifton uniqueness theorem (1996) for 'no collapse' interpretations of quantum mechanics can be proved without the 'weak separability' assumption.