Scuola Normale Superiore
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1989
Lugano, Ticino, Switzerland
Areas of Specialization
Metaphysics and Epistemology
Value Theory
  •  7
    Raffigurazioni senza finzioni
    Rivista di Estetica 40 71-83. 2009.
    In svariate occasioni (1973, 1990, 2002) Kendall Walton ha sostenuto una teoria della raffigurazione basata sul concetto di far finta: P raffigura (almeno) solo se per il fatto di avere un’esperienza percettiva di P, si fa finta che tale esperienza sia l’esperienza percettiva del soggetto rappresentato da P. Una conseguenza di questa teoria è che, se un individuo non sa far finta, allora ciò con cui si confronta direttamente nella percezione non è una raffigurazione per lui. Ci sono però molt...
  •  3
    In (1990), Jerry Fodor has defended a naturalized conception of meaning for Mentalese expressions which relies on the notion of asymmetric dependence. According to this conception, any naturalized theory of meaning must be able to account for the fact that meaning is robust, namely that any token of a certain Mentalese expression “x” retains the expression’s meaning, X, for any Y (≠ X) which happens to cause it. Now, this robustness of “x”‘s meaning can precisely be explained in terms of the sub…Read more
  •  6
    From Hegel to Kaplan
    In C. Penco & G. Sarbia (eds.), Alle radici della filosofia analitica, Erga. pp. 825-850. 1996.
    Da Hegel fino a Bradley, l'attacco idealista ad una concezione pluralistica della realtà come una credenza non suffragata dalla verità delle cose si è valso dell'argomento semantico secondo il quale le espressioni indicali, su cui da ultimo riposerebbe tutta la valenza referenziale del linguaggio, non si riferiscono a segmenti discreti del reale ma si limitano ad esprimere universali. Dal versante ontologico opposto, Russell ha guidato la reazione all'idealismo assoluto (inaugurando così uno dei…Read more
  •  6
    In one of its latest papers Timothy Williamson has drawn a distinction between two readings of the phrase "possible F", where "F" is a predicate variable: the predicative and the attributive. In what follows, on the one hand I will hold that the first reading naturally applies to the phrase "possible object", thereby supporting a moderata conception of possibilia as entities that possibly exist. Moreover, I will maintain that one such conception provides the best possible account of Tractarian o…Read more
  •  58
    Introduction
    with Stefano Di Bella, Mauro Mariani, and Giuseppe Varnier
    Topoi 19 (2): 77-82. 2000.
  •  21
    Introduzione
    with Carola Barbero and Mario De Caro
    Rivista di Estetica 44 3-5. 2010.
    “Naturalismo” è una parola che si dice in molti modi, almeno tanti quanti nella storia della filosofia e nel sentire comune sono i modi in cui si è parlato di “natura” e di espressioni simili. Oggi, il tema del naturalismo in filosofia e della cosiddetta naturalizzazione che una filosofia dovrebbe eventualmente attrezzare determinate nozioni e teorie è tornato prepotentemente alla ribalta della riflessione filosofica, sulla scia dei successi provenienti dalle scienze cognitive (linguistica, n...
  •  9
    Book reviews (review)
    Acta Analytica 18 (1-2): 231-240. 2003.
  •  27
    In che cosa consiste far finta
    Aisthesis: Pratiche, Linguaggi E Saperi Dell’Estetico 2 (2). 2009.
  •  734
    Puns for Contextualists
    Humana Mente 5 (23): 113-140. 2012.
    In this paper, I will first try to provide a new argument in favour of the contextualist position on the semantics/pragmatics divide. I will argue that many puns, notably multi-stable ones, cannot be dealt with in the non-contextualist way, i.e., as displaying a phenomenon that effectively involves wide context, the concrete situation of discourse, yet only in a pre-, or at least inter-, semantic sense. For, insofar as they involve ambiguous utterances rather than ambiguous sentences, these puns…Read more
  •  76
    Why, as responsible for figurativity, seeing-in can only be inflected seeing-in
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 14 (3): 651-667. 2015.
    In this paper, I want to argue for two main and related points. First, I want to defend Richard Wollheim’s well-known thesis that the twofold mental state of seeing-in is the distinctive pictorial experience that marks figurativity. Figurativity is what makes a representation pictorial, a depiction of its subject. Moreover, I want to show that insofar as it is a mark of figurativity, all seeing-in is inflected. That is to say, every mental state of seeing-in is such that the characterisation of …Read more
  •  29
    How to Allow for Intentionalia in the Jungle
    Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 27 (1): 86-105. 2007.
    Abstract:In this paper I will first contend that semantically based arguments in favour of or against problematic entities—like those provided, respectively, in a realist Meinongian and in an antirealist Russellian camp—are ultimately inconclusive. Indeed, only genuinely ontological arguments, specifically addressed to prove (or to reject) the existence of entities of a definite kind, suit the purpose. Thus, I will sketch an argument intended to show that there really are entities of an apparent…Read more
  •  46
    A Syncretistic Theory of Depiction
    Palgrave-Macmillan. 2015.
    What is depiction? This is a venerable question that has received many different answers throughout the whole history of philosophy, especially in contemporary times. A Syncretistic Theory of Depiction elaborates a new account on this matter by providing a theory of depiction that tries to combine the merits of the previous theories while dropping their defects. It is argued that a picture is a representation in a pictorial or figurative mode, and its 'figurativity' is given by a special percept…Read more
  •  16
    The depicted gaze of the Other
    Rivista di Estetica 56 111-126. 2014.
    In this paper, I first want to vindicate Wollheim’s idea that seeing-in, taken as the twofold phenomenologically sui generis experience which picture perception consists in, accounts for the phenomenon of perceptual constancy. Following Wollheim’s usage himself, by “perceptual constancy” I will mean a particular phenomenon of perceptual robustness, namely the fact that a picture’s subject is experienced as undistorted from any point of view in which a spectator may regard a picture. Moreover, I …Read more
  •  64
  •  60
    Guises and their existence
    Axiomathes 7 (3): 419-434. 1996.
    According to H-N. Castañeda, a guise - the very thin individual which lies at the bottom of the ontological furniture of the world - is indifferent to existence in a Meinongian way, in the sense that it remains the same whether it exists or not. Moreover, its existence does not alter its intentional character, as it is the very same individual which is thought of regardless of its being real or not1. In what follows, I will attempt to show that with regards to guises both theses are illegitimate…Read more
  •  34
    In this paper, we first want to defend the idea that reference intentionality is the relation of constitution holding between an intentional state, a thought, and the object it is about, its intentional object. As such, reference intentionality is for a thought an essential property, whose predication to that thought is true in virtue of the nature of such a thought. We will take this to be one of the main lessons of serious externalism, according to which the intentional object occurs in the in…Read more
  •  142
    Fiction as a Base of Interpretation Contexts
    Synthese 153 (1): 23-47. 2006.
    In this paper, I want to deal with the problem of how to find an adequate context of interpretation for indexical sentences that enables one to account for the intuitive truth-conditional content which some apparently puzzling indexical sentences like “I am not here now” as well as other such sentences contextually have. In this respect, I will pursue a fictionalist line. This line allows for shifts in interpretation contexts and urges that such shifts are governed by pretense, which has to be u…Read more
  •  98
    Objects as Intentional and as Real
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 41 (1): 1-32. 1991.
    A theory of intentionality is outlined, in which the desideratum that the intentional be the same as the real object is argued for in terms of an anti-realist ontology. According to such an ontology, an ordinary object is in itself an object of discourse taken as intentional when posited phenomenologically and as possible when posited naturalistically, i.e. as not existing in some possible worlds but as existing in others. If the actual world is included among the latter, the object deserves to …Read more
  •  38
    Il migliore dei naturalismi possibili
    with Mario De Caro
    Rivista di Estetica 44 157-169. 2010.
    In this paper, we first set out three requirements that each e-theory – a theory whose task is to explain data – must fulfill in order to be one such good theory: i) an ontological requirement, i.e. adequate simplicity, ii) a methodological requirement, i.e. plurality of research procedures, iii) an epistemological requirement, i.e. compatibility with the best available epistemical procedures. Moreover, we will claim that from the metaphilosophical point of view, unlike scientific naturalism on …Read more
  •  2
    Critical notice of: François Recanati, Direct Reference (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993) (review)
    European Review of Philosophy 2 175-184. 1997.
    Everything you wanted to know about direct reference and always dared to ask is contained in Recanati's new book, which is not only a comprehensive survey on the received doctrine but also an original attempt to find a new way out of the many puzzles which surround the "new theory of reference" (in H. Wettstein's words) since its origins. Principles and conceptions are indeed acutely specified and Recanati's own theses are argued for in a very subtle and rigorous way. One cannot leave the volume…Read more
  •  512
    Along with a well-honoured tradition, we will accept that intentionality is at least a property a thought holds necessarily, i.e., in all possible worlds that contain it; more specifically, a necessary relation, namely the relation of existential dependence of the thought on its intentional object. Yet we will first of all try to show that intentionality is more than that. For we will claim that intentionality is an essential property of the thought, namely a property whose predication to the th…Read more
  •  1
    Was Wittgenstein Wrong About Intentionality?
    In P. Frascolla, D. Marconi & A. Voltolini (eds.), Wittgenstein: Mind, Meaning and Metaphilosophy, Palgrave. pp. 67-81. 2010.
    At least prima facie, there is no doubt that the later Wittgenstein conceived intentionality as a normative notion, where the normativity in question is of a linguistic kind. As he repeatedly says, the (internal) agreement between thought and reality that makes a particular subsisting state of affairs be the fulfilment of a certain intentional state is to be found in language, and language is intrinsically normative. Or, to put it more precisely, it is a rule of grammar that the intentional stat…Read more
  •  6
    Wittgensteinian watered-down qualia
    In A. Coliva & E. Picardi (eds.), Wittgenstein Today, Il Poligrafo. pp. 335-352. 2004.
    In this paper I want to hold that Wittgenstein’s later position on qualitative states, which sees them as triplets made out of three necessary components - stimulus, qualitative element and manifestability - allows for supervenience of such states over physical ones. Insofar as this is the case, such a position is more akin to naturalism that the one that has been recently defended by Kim, who allows for merely partial supervenience of qualia over physical states. Moreover, Wittgenstein’s concep…Read more
  •  1
    Indexinames
    In J. Hill & P. Kot'attko (eds.), Karlovy Vary Studies in Reference and Meaning, Filosofia. pp. 258-285. 1995.
    Insofar as the so-called new theory of reference has come to be acknowleged as the leading theoretical paradigm in semantic research, it has been widely accepted that proper names directly refer to their designation. In advancing some of the most convincing arguments in favour of this view of names, S. Kripke has however left somehow undecided what the role of context is in determining which is the direct referent for a name. According to one interpretation of his thought, context has only an ex…Read more
  •  494
    Defiction?
    In C. Barbero, M. Ferraris & A. Voltolini (eds.), From Fictionalism to Realism, Cambridge Scholars Press. 2013.
    On various occasions, Kendall Walton has put forward a theory of depiction based on the notion of make-believe: P depicts something only if in virtue of having a perception of P, one makes believe that that very experience is the perception of P’s subject. As a consequence, if an individual is not able to make believe, whatever they face in their perception does not count as a depiction for her. Yet there are many evidences from developmental psychology that show that very little children still …Read more
  •  122
    The Seven Consequences of Creationism
    Metaphysica 10 (1): 27-48. 2009.
    Creationism with respect to fictional entities, i.e., the position according to which ficta are creations of human practices, has recently become the most popular realist account of fictional entities. For it allows one to hold that there are fictional entities while simultaneously giving such entities a respectable metaphysical status, that of abstract artifacts. In this paper, I will draw what are the ontological and semantical consequences of this position, or at least of all its forms that a…Read more