University Tübingen
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 2009
Tübingen, Baden-Württemberg, Germany
  •  10
  •  5256
    Pierre Duhem gilt ais einer der wichtigsten Reprüsentanten der franzosischen Wissenschaftsphilosophie um 1900. Seine Konzeption physikalischer Theorien wird üblicherweise ais moderne Umsetzung des antiken – proto-positivistischen – Programms der „Rettung der Phänomene‟ angesehen. Diese Sicht ist richtig, bedarf aber der Ergänzung, indem der diskursive Kontext der Duhemschen Position berücksichtigt wird. Im vorliegenden Beitrag wird dargelegt, dass Duhems philosophischer Zeitgenosse Abel Rey eine…Read more
  •  31
    Helmholtz, Kaila, and the Representational Theory of Measurement
    Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 8 (2): 409-431. 2018.
    The problem of measurement can be reformulated as the problem of measurability: What are the conditions under which measurement becomes possible at all? And what is the ontological status of concrete measurement outcomes? It will be shown in the course of this article that what Joel Michell deemed the ‘representational theory’ of measurement provides an adequate framework for answering these questions. However, contrary to Michell, I will point out that Hermann von Helmholtz should be seen as an…Read more
  •  13
    ,,Denn was man messen kann, das existiert auch." Grundzüge eines metrologischen Strukturenrealismus
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 72 (1): 50-74. 2018.
  •  178
    Perception and Coincidence in Helmholtz’s Theory of Measurement
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 6 (3). 2018.
    The present paper is concerned with Helmholtz’s theory of measurement. It will be argued that an adequate understanding of this theory depends on how Helmholtz’s application of the concepts of perception and coincidence is interpreted. In contrast both to conventionalist and Kantian readings of Helmholtz’s theory, a more realistic interpretation will be suggested.
  •  26
    Mathematik und Ontologie. Der lange Weg zum,strukturellen Formalismus'
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 71 (3): 358-379. 2017.
  •  20
    Treffpunkt Struktur – Cassirer, Schlick und Carnap
    Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 95 (2): 206-233. 2013.
    Structure is the connecting link between the early epistemologies of Cassirer, Schlick, and Carnap. However, there are important programmatic differences among Cassirer’s, Schlick’s, and Carnap’s articulations of the structuralistic point of view. Whereas Cassirer hoped to argue in favor of an ‚idealist‘ and Schlick in favor of a ‚realist‘ conception of structure, Carnap thought it possible to remain neutral in this respect. I will argue that Carnap’s approach, though at first sight promising, w…Read more
  •  15
    Torsten Wilholt: Die Freiheit der Forschung: Begrenzungen und Begründungen
    Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 44 (2): 397-399. 2013.
    Torsten Wilholt’s book on the freedom of research is a remarkable contribution to a long-standing debate over an issue which is becoming increasingly important today. As Wilholt points out in the preface, the topic ‘freedom of research’ has a twofold face: On the one hand, freedom of research is the presupposition of an engaged and unprejudiced search for knowledge; on the other hand, it implies the risk of borderless and ‘untamed’ research. In considering this contradiction, Wilholt makes recou…Read more
  • Raum-Zeit (review)
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 65 (3). 2011.
  •  9
    Phänomenologie, Neukantianismus und logischer Empirismus waren die dominanten Strömungen in der deutschsprachigen theoretischen Philosophie des frühen 20. Jahrhunderts. Die Beziehungen dieser drei philosophischen Positionen untereinander wurden in der philosophiehistorischen Forschung bisher allenfalls in Teilkonstellationen untersucht. Der Band liefert erstmals eine Zusammenschau dieser drei Positionen. Die Autoren gehen in ihren Aufsätzen der Frage auf den Grund, wie die Beziehungen zueinander…Read more
  •  27
  •  21
    Heinz Steinert: Max Webers unwiderlegbare Fehlkonstruktionen. Die protestantische Ethik und der Geist des Kapitalismus
    with Heinz Steinert
    Philosophischer Literaturanzeiger 67 (4): 369-372. 2014.
  •  17
    It is a common view in cognitive psychology that there is a fundamental difference between what may be called descriptive information, on the one hand, and depictive information, on the other. While the first kind of information is — ideally spoken — non-pictorial and usually equated with the content of a proposition, the second kind of information is pictorial by defmition and accordingly equated with the content of a mental image. Granting the correctness of this distinction, cognitive scienti…Read more
  • Rezension von Esfeld 2008
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 62 (3): 457-461. 2008.
  •  786
    Dogmenfreiheit als Prinzip? Neuere Literatur zum logischen Empirismus
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 65 (1): 96-114. 2011.
  •  26
    Michael Esfeld und Christian Sachse: Kausale Strukturen. Einheit und Vielfalt in der Natur und den Naturwissenschaften (review)
    Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 42 (2): 415-419. 2011.
  •  32
  •  17
    Volker Kruse, Uwe Barrelmeyer: Max Weber. Eine Einführung
    Philosophischer Literaturanzeiger 65 (4): 312-318. 2012.
  •  29
    Is Logical Empiricism Compatible with Scientific Realism?
    In Maria Carla Galavotti, Elisabeth Nemeth & Friedrich Stadler (eds.), European Philosophy of Science: Philosophy of Science in Europe and the Vienna Heritage, Springer. pp. 249-262. 2014.
    Scientific realism is the view that the theoretical entities of science exist. Atoms, forces, electromagnetic fields, and so on, are not merely instruments for organizing observational data but are real and causally effective. This view seems to be hardly compatible with the logical empiricist agenda: As common wisdom has it, logical empiricism is mainly characterized by a strong verification criterion of meaning, i.e., by the project of defining the meaning of theoretical terms by virtue of the…Read more
  •  69
    Rudolf Carnap’s role in the debate over scientific realism is fairly unclear. In a certain sense, Carnap must be regarded as the one who rendered the whole issue irrelevant. However, it cannot be ignored that Carnap sometimes spoke of himself as an ‘empirical realist.’ So the question to be answered is: in what sense, if at all, did Carnap play a constructive role in the scientific realism debate. It is the aim of the present paper to tackle this question by investigating the relationship betwee…Read more
  •  57
    Helmholtz's Theory of Space and its Significance for Schlick
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (1). 2012.
    Helmholtz's theory of space had significant impact on Schlick's early ?critical realist? point of view. However, it will be argued in this paper that Schlick's appropriation of Helmholtz's ideas eventually lead to a rather radical transformation of the original Helmholtzian position
  •  17
    Die Kulturphilosophie Ernst Cassirers. Neuere Forschungstrends und -perspektiven
    Latest Issue of Philosophische Rundschau 63 (2): 123-142. 2016.
  •  1023
    Realistic Claims in Logical Empiricism
    In Uskali Mäki, Stéphanie Ruphy, Gerhard Schurz & Ioannis Votsis (eds.), Recent Developments in the Philosophy of Science, Springer. 2015.
    Logical empiricism is commonly seen as a counter-position to scientific realism. In the present paper it is shown that there indeed existed a realist faction within the logical empiricist movement. In particular, I shall point out that at least four types of realistic arguments can be distinguished within this faction: Reichenbach’s ‘probabilistic argument,’ Feigl’s ‘pragmatic argument,’ Hempel’s ‘indispensability argument,’ and Kaila’s ‘invariantist argument.’ All these variations of arguments …Read more
  •  19
    In their early epistemological writings, Cassirer and Schlick represent two different strategies in their revisionist approaches toward the original Kantian doctrine. While Cassirer attempts a revision in the sense of ‚critical idealism‘, Schlick attempts a revision in the sense of ‚critical realism‘. It will be shown that this contrast in programmatic outlook leads to significant divergences, especially in the respective theories of space and the correlated interpretations of Einstein's general…Read more
  •  20
    "Die Grenzen des Revisionismus" befasst sich mit den erkenntnis- und wissenschafttheoretischen Positionen des frühen Moritz Schlick und des frühen Ernst Cassirer