Andy Clark

This is a database entry with public information about a philosopher who is not a registered user of PhilPeople.
  •  459
    The twisted matrix: Dream, simulation, or hybrid?
    In C. Grau (ed.), Philosophical Essays on the Matrix, Oxford University Press New York. 2005.
    “The Matrix is a computer-generated dreamworld built to keep us under control” Morpheus, early in The Matrix. “ In dreaming, you are not only out of control, you don’t even know it…I was completely duped again and again the minute my pons, my amygdala, my perihippocampal cortex, my anterior cingulate, my visual association and parietal opercular cortices were revved up and my dorsolateral prefrontal cortex was muffled” ” J. Allan Hobson, The Dream Drugstore, p.64 The Matrix is an exercise in amb…Read more
  •  364
    Visual awareness and visuomotor action
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 6 (11-12): 1-18. 1999.
    Recent work in "embodied, embedded" cognitive science links mental contents to large-scale distributed effects: dynamic patterns implicating elements of (what are traditionally seen as) sensing, reasoning and acting. Central to this approach is an idea of biological cognition as profoundly "action-oriented" - geared not to the creation of rich, passive inner models of the world, but to the cheap and efficient production of real-world action in real-world context. A case in point is Hurley's (199…Read more
  •  652
    Visual experience and motor action: Are the bonds too tight?
    Philosophical Review 110 (4): 495-519. 2001.
    How should we characterize the functional role of conscious visual experience? In particular, how do the conscious contents of visual experience guide, bear upon, or otherwise inform our ongoing motor activities? According to an intuitive and (I shall argue) philosophically influential conception, the links are often quite direct. The contents of conscious visual experience, according to this conception, are typically active in the control and guidance of our fine-tuned, real-time engagements wi…Read more
  •  113
    Intentionality and information
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65 (3): 335-341. 1987.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  89
    Phenomenal immediacy and the doors of sensation
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 7 (4): 21-24. 2000.
    [opening paragraph]: Nicholas Humphrey offers a refreshingly progressive recipe for laying wide the doors of sensation: for understanding the peculiar features of qualitative or sensational experience in terms of the physical or functional facts about brains, bodies and environments. The key move in the treatment is the promotion of a kind of co- ordinated, double-sided tweaking: a careful restatement, with some amendments, of each side of the elusive identity statement ‘sensational property x =…Read more
  •  43
    Belief, opinion and consciousness
    Philosophical Psychology 3 (1): 139-154. 1990.
    Abstract The paper considers two recent accounts of the difference between human and animal thought. One deflationary account, due to Daniel Dennett, insists that the only real difference lies in our ability to use words and sentences to give artificial precision and determinacy to our mental contents. The other, due to Paul Smolensky, conjectures that we at times deploy a special purpose device (the Conscious Rule Interpreter) whose task is to deal with public, symbolically coded data and comma…Read more
  •  439
    A case where access implies qualia?
    Analysis 60 (1): 30-37. 2000.
    Block (1995) famously warns against the confusion of.
  •  389
    That Special Something: Dennett on the Making of Minds and Selves
    In Andrew Brook & Don Ross (eds.), Daniel Dennett, Cambridge University Press. pp. 187--205. 2002.
    Dennett depicts human minds as both deeply different from, yet profoundly continuous with, the minds of other animals and simple agents. His treatments of mind, consciousness, free will and human agency all reflect this distinctive dual perspective. There is, on the one hand, the (in)famous Intentional Stance, relative to which humans, dogs, insects and even the lowly thermostat (e.g. Dennett (1998) p.327) are all pronounced capable of believing and desiring in essentially the same theoretical s…Read more
  •  5
    On Executive Attention
    PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 15 (1). 2009.
    In her excellent and thought-provoking essay ";Searching for the Source of Executive Attention";; Catherine Stinson argues that many accounts of executive attention threaten to involve some kind of conceptual confusion. While agreeing with many of the key criticisms, I explore some possible responses, which retain some of the flavor of the notion of executive attention
  • Od Heideggera ke kognitivní vědě
    Filosoficky Casopis 48 1049-1053. 2000.
    [From Heidegger to Cognitive Science]
  •  1
    Negotiating Embodiment
    Janus Head 9 (2): 585-587. 2007.
  •  6
    Linguistic anchors in the sea of thought?
    Pragmatics and Cognition 4 (1): 93-103. 1995.
    Language, according to Jackendoff, is more than just an instrument of communication and cultural transmission. It is also a tool which helps us to think. It does so, he suggests, by expanding the range of our conscious contents and hence allowing processes of attention and reflection to focus on items which would not otherwise be available for scrutiny. I applaud Jackendoff s basic vision, but raise some doubts concerning the argument. In particular, I wonder what it is about public language tha…Read more
  •  21
    Markets, companies and various forms of business organizations may all be usefully viewed through the lens of CAS -- the theory of complex adaptive systems. In this chapter, I address one fundamental issue that confronts both the theoretician and the business manager: the nature and opportunities for control and intervention in complex adaptive regimes. The problem is obvious enough. A complex adaptive system, as we have defined it, is soft assembled and largely self-organizing. This means that …Read more
  •  38
    What is the relation between perceptual experience and the suite of sensorimotor skills that enable us to act in the very world we perceive? The relation, according to ‘sensorimotor models’ is tight indeed. Perceptual experience, on these accounts, is enacted via skilled sensorimotor activity, and gains its content and character courtesy of our knowledge of the relations between movement and sensory stimulation. I shall argue that this formulation is too extreme, and that it fails to accommodate…Read more
  •  18
    Author’s response
    with Chris Thornton
    Metascience 7 (1): 95-104. 1998.
  •  743
    How to situate cognition: Letting nature take its course
    In Murat Aydede & P. Robbins (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition, Cambridge University Press. pp. 55--77. 2009.
    1. The Situation in Cognition 2. Situated Cognition: A Potted Recent History 3. Extensions in Biology, Computation, and Cognition 4. Articulating the Idea of Cognitive Extension 5. Are Some Resources Intrinsically Non-Cognitive? 6. Is Cognition Extended or Only Embedded? 7. Letting Nature Take Its Course
  •  66
    Mind: Natural, artificial, hybrid, and “super”
    with Blade Runner, Isaac Asimov, Ned Block, and Daniel C. Dennett
    In Susan Schneider (ed.), Science Fiction and Philosophy: From Time Travel to Superintelligence, Wiley-blackwell. 2009.
  •  13
    Putting Concepts to Work: Some Thoughts for the Twentyfirst Century
    with Jesse Prinz and Jerry Fodor
    Mind and Language 19 (1): 57-69. 2004.
    Fodor's theory makes thinking prior to doing. It allows for an inactive agent or pure reflector, and for agents whose actions in various ways seem to float free of their own conceptual repertoires. We show that naturally evolved creatures are not like that. In the real world, thinking is always and everywhere about doing. The point of having a brain is to guide the actions of embodied beings in a complex material world. Some of those actions are, to be sure, more recondite than others. But in ev…Read more
  •  300
    Is seeing all it seems? Action, reason and the grand illusion
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 9 (5-6): 181-202. 2002.
    We seem, or so it seems to some theorists, to experience a rich stream of highly detailed information concerning an extensive part of our current visual surroundings. But this appearance, it has been suggested, is in some way illusory. Our brains do not command richly detailed internal models of the current scene. Our seeings, it seems, are not all that they seem. This, then, is the Grand Illusion. We think we see much more than we actually do. In this paper I shall (briefly) rehearse the empiri…Read more
  •  7
    This is the first of two volumes of essays on the intellectual legacy of Alan Turing, whose pioneering work in artificial intelligence and computer science made him one of the seminal thinkers of the century. A distinguished international cast of contributors focus on the three famous ideas associated with his name: the Turing test, the Turing machine, and the Church-Turing thesis. 'a fascinating series of essays on computation by contributors in many fields' Choice
  •  1093
    The Extended Mind Thesis
    with Kiverstein Julian and Mirko Farina
    Oxford Bibliographies Online. forthcoming.
  •  605
    Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (3): 181-204. 2013.
    Brains, it has recently been argued, are essentially prediction machines. They are bundles of cells that support perception and action by constantly attempting to match incoming sensory inputs with top-down expectations or predictions. This is achieved using a hierarchical generative model that aims to minimize prediction error within a bidirectional cascade of cortical processing. Such accounts offer a unifying model of perception and action, illuminate the functional role of attention, and may…Read more
  •  190
    What ‘Extended Me’ knows
    Synthese 192 (11): 3757-3775. 2015.
    Arguments for the ‘extended mind’ seem to suggest the possibility of ‘extended knowers’—agents whose specifically epistemic virtues may depend on systems whose boundaries are not those of the brain or the biological organism. Recent discussions of this possibility invoke insights from virtue epistemology, according to which knowledge is the result of the application of some kind of cognitive skill or ability on the part of the agent. In this paper, I argue that there is a fundamental tension in …Read more
  •  520
    Word and Action: Reconciling Rules and Know-How in Moral Cognition
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30 (sup1): 267-289. 2000.
    Recent work in cognitive science highlights the importance of exem- plar-based know-how in supporting human expertise. Influenced by this model, certain accounts of moral knowledge now stress exemplar- based, non-sentential know-how at the expense of rule-and-principle based accounts. I shall argue, however, that moral thought and reason cannot be understood by reference to either of these roles alone. Moral cognition – like other forms of ‘advanced’ cognition – depends crucially on the subtle i…Read more
  •  632
    Vision as dance? Three challenges for sensorimotor contingency theory
    PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 12. 2006.
    In _Action in Perception _Alva No develops and presents a sensorimotor account of vision and of visual consciousness. According to such an account seeing (and indeed perceiving more generally) is analysed as a kind of skilful bodily activity. Such a view is consistent with the emerging emphasis, in both philosophy and cognitive science, on the critical role of embodiment in the construction of intelligent agency. I shall argue, however, that the full sensorimotor model faces three important chal…Read more
  •  48
    It is widely appreciated that the difficulty of a particluar computation varies according to how the input data are presented. What is less understood is the effect of this computation/representation tradeoff within familiar learning paradigms. We argue that existing learning algoritms are often poorly equipped to solve problems involving a certain type of important and widespread regularity, which we call 'type-2' regularity. The solution in these cases is to trade achieved representation again…Read more