Temple University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1974
Iowa City, Iowa, United States of America
  •  72
    World without design: The ontological consequences of naturalism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (2): 494-497. 2005.
  •  64
    Antediluvian Theodicy
    Faith and Philosophy 6 (3): 320-329. 1989.
    This paper is a discussion of Eleonore Stump’s “The Problem of Evil.” Stump, I argue, has attempted a theodicy with several desirable features; among them, an effort to provide a positive account of the compatibility of natural evils with God’s goodness that makes use of specifically Christian doctrines. However, the doctrines Stump makes use of---and, in particular, her conception of hell and her interpretation of original sin---raise, I suggest, more problems than they solve.
  •  60
    Theoretical simplicity and defeasibility
    Philosophy of Science 45 (2): 273-288. 1978.
    Theoretical simplicity is difficult to characterize, and evidently can depend upon a number of distinct factors. One such desirable characteristic is that the laws of a theory have relatively few "counterinstances" whose accommodation requires the invocation of a ceteris paribus condition and ancillary explanation. It is argued that, when one theory is reduced to another, such that the laws of the second govern the behavior of the parts of the entities in the domain of the first, there is a char…Read more
  •  48
    Several writers have argued for the implausibility of there being naturalistic explanations of mystical experience. These writers recognize that the evidential significance of mystical experiences for theism depends upon whether explanations that exclude supernatural agency can be discounted; but they seem unaware of some of the best scientific work done in this area. Part I of the present paper introduces the theory of I. M. Lewis, an anthropologist, and tests it against the case of St Teresa. …Read more
  •  47
    Darwin’s Doubt, Calvin’s Calvary
    In Michael Ruse (ed.), Philosophy After Darwin: Classic and Contemporary Readings, Princeton University Press. pp. 309-322. 2009.
  •  47
    How to Be a Metaphysical Realist
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1): 253-274. 1988.
  •  45
    Scientific explanations of mystical experiences: Evan Fales
    Religious Studies 32 (3): 297-313. 1996.
    In Part I of this paper, I took up a challenge posed by Alston , Wainwright , Yandell , and other theists who hold the rather natural view that mystical experiences provide perceptual contact with God, roughly on a par with the access sense experience affords to the natural world. These theists recognize, at the same time, that the plausibility of this view would be significantly compromised by the possibility of scientifically explaining mystical experiences – especially if a scientific explana…Read more
  •  45
    Relative essentialism
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (4): 349-370. 1979.
  •  43
    It has become something of a leitmotif among evangelical apologetes to argue that morality can have no objective foundation if there is no God. Using a strategy that appeals to many people's strong intuitions that there are objective rights and wrongs, they claim seek to convict atheists of being intellectually committed to moral relativism, subjectivism, or nihilism. Those are, of course, ethical positions that have been advocated by some atheists. But others share the intuition that there are …Read more
  •  40
    Are Christians Obliged to Be Pacifists?
    Faith and Philosophy 11 (2): 298-301. 1994.
  •  40
    Generic universals
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (1). 1982.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  35
    Review of Stewart Goetz, Freedom, Teleology, and Evil (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (8). 2009.
  •  34
    Opacity in the Attitudes
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (4). 1978.
    Philosophical logic has its problem-children; and among these the Principle of Substitutivity of codesignating expressions — the linguistic spawn of Leibniz's law—has achieved a place of prominence. It has become increasingly apparent that a certain style of linguistic analysis, which seeks to impose formal regimentation ruled by the constraints of classical quantification theory, does not yield results with the kind of uniformity and elegance one should hope for from a satisfyi.ng theory. The r…Read more
  •  32
    The Case for Humanism: An Introduction
    with Lewis Vaughn and Austin Dacey
    Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. 2003.
    The Case for Humanism is the premier textbook to introduce and help students think critically about the 'big ideas' of Western humanism—secularism, rationalism, materialism, science, democracy, individualism, and others—all powerful themes that run through Western thought from the ancient Greeks and the Enlightenment to the present day
  •  30
    The Epistemology of Spirit Beliefs, written by Hans Van Eyghen
    International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 14 (1): 79-85. 2023.
  •  28
    This study is a new look at the question of how God can act upon the world, and whether the world can affect God, examining contemporary work on the metaphysics of causation and laws of nature, and current work in the theory of knowledge and mysticism. It has been traditional to address such questions by appealing to God’s omnipotence and omniscience, but this book claims that this is useless unless it can be shown how these two powers "work." Instead of treating the familiar problems associated…Read more
  •  21
    Causation and Induction
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9 (1): 113-134. 1984.
  •  19
    "Causation: A Realist Approach" by Michael Tooley (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (3): 605. 1990.
  •  19
    Successful Defense? (review)
    Philosophia Christi 3 (1): 7-35. 2001.
  •  17
    Causation: A Realist Approach
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (3): 605-610. 1990.
  •  17
    Causes and Coincidences (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2): 465-468. 1995.
  •  14
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 103 (411): 391-395. 1994.
  •  11
    Theodicy in a Vale of Tears
    In Justin P. McBrayer & Daniel Howard‐Snyder (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil, Wiley. 2013.
    Theodicies can be distinguished as “hard-nosed” or “good-hearted.” Typical features of each are given. I reject the former; they set the bar too low for God. Considerable discussion is devoted to Eleonore Stump's recent Wandering in Darkness, which sets the standard for good-hearted theodicies. I then develop the notion of a “perfect creature”, a possible being indistinguishable from God except lacking aseity, and argue that God should have created only perfect creatures. Since He did not, He is…Read more
  •  10
    Causes and Coincidences (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2): 465-468. 1995.
  •  9
    Book review (review)
    Foundations of Physics 14 (1): 89-99. 1984.