•  33
    Plato’s Invisible Cities (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 13 (2): 427-430. 1993.
  • Plato's Thoughts and Literature
    Dissertation, Harvard University. 1987.
    This dissertation brings Plato's critique of poetry to bear on the issue of how to read his dialogues. Since antiquity commentators on Plato have debated the extent to which he actually meant the philosophical doctrines in his works; since the early nineteenth century this debate has been complicated by the claim that the dialogues count as literature. To treat them as literature is to hold, in a subtler sense, that Plato does not himself assert what their characters say. ;I therefore categorize…Read more
  •  30
    Plato's Myths
    Philosophical Inquiry 34 (1-2): 101-106. 2011.
  •  26
    Plato on Justice and Power: Reading Book I of Plato's Republic
    with Kimon Lycos
    Philosophical Review 100 (3): 515. 1991.
  •  156
    Plato on Poetry: Imitation or Inspiration?
    Philosophy Compass 7 (10): 669-678. 2012.
    A passage in Plato’s Laws (719c) offers a fresh look at Plato’s theory of poetry and art. Only here does Plato call poetry both mimêsis “imitation, representation,” and the product of enthousiasmos “inspiration, possession.” The Republic and Sophist examine poetic imitation; the Ion and Phaedrus (with passages in Apology and Meno) develop a theory of artistic inspiration; but Plato does not confront the two descriptions together outside this paragraph. After all, mimêsis fuels an attack on poetr…Read more
  •  54
    Mimêsis in Aristophanes and Plato
    Philosophical Inquiry 21 (3-4): 61-78. 1999.
  •  18
    Nietzsche's Apollo
    Journal of Nietzsche Studies 45 (1): 43-53. 2014.
    Two great evaluative questions about The Birth of Tragedy ask how accurate the book is about Greece’s “tragic age,” and how nostalgic it is for that age. Wilamowitz raised the question of accuracy as soon as the book was published, and the issue has never gone away. As for nostalgia, even without accepting extreme versions of the charge, you can still worry that BT portrays Socrates as such a calamity—a monstrosity, and therefore a freakish birth, something that did not have to happen—as to invi…Read more
  •  30
    Philhellenism and Greek Philosophy
    Philosophical Forum 32 (2): 165-173. 2001.
  •  37
    Morality Gags
    The Monist 88 (1): 52-71. 2005.
    It was in the year of Nietzsche’s death that Bergson published Laughter, but he had been thinking about the subject while Nietzsche was alive and active. In 1884 he delivered a lecture, “Le rire: de quoi rit-on? Pourquoi rit-on?”; the book Le Rire grew from that lecture and enlarged its inquiry into what one laughs at and why, even if the book still does not probe deeply enough into who that “one” is who’s laughing.
  •  18
    Commentary on Frede
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 12 (1): 277-284. 1996.
  •  66
    Fancy justice: Martha Nussbaum on the political value of the novel
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78 (3). 1997.
    Martha Nussbaum's Poetic Justice undertakes a defense of the novel by showing it to develop the sympathetic imagination. Three parts of her argument come in for criticism, with implications for other such political defenses. Nussbaum sometimes interprets the imagination practically, sometimes theoretically; the two forms have different effects on deliberation. Nussbaum credits the novelistic tradition with fostering the imagination; her example of Hard Times interferes with establishing this gen…Read more
  •  161
    Fashion Seen as Something Imitative and Foreign
    British Journal of Aesthetics 48 (1): 1-19. 2008.
    Philosophers have recently begun to write about fashion in dress. They acknowledge that philosophy traditionally ignored the subject altogether or else disparaged fashion. They do not observe that those past philosophers who slighted fashion characterized it as mass imitativeness; but in fact that one-sided characterization is what permitted commentators to overlook innovativeness in fashion. Indeed the figure of the foreigner that recurs in philosophical remarks about fashion only makes sense g…Read more
  •  39
    Autochthony in Plato's Menexenus
    Philosophical Inquiry 34 (1-2): 66-80. 2011.
  •  36
    Authorship and authority
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 47 (4): 325-332. 1989.
  • Aristotle
    In Berys Nigel Gaut & Dominic Lopes (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics, Routledge. 2000.
  •  15
    Beautiful City: The Dialectical Character of Plato's Republic (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (2): 218-219. 2004.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 42.2 (2004) 218-219 [Access article in PDF] David Roochnik. Beautiful City: The Dialectical Character of Plato's Republic. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2003. Pp. ix + 159. Cloth, $35.00. Plato makes no general assertions, certainly none about "universals" (108). The Republic does not advocate the creation of an ideal state (78, 93) but transcends utopias to acknowledge the merits of democracy…Read more
  •  18
    Knowing and Saying That I Know
    Philosophy 66 (258). 1991.
    Of course there's every difference in the world between my merely saying something and its being so. My claim that I have a toothache is a far cry from the toothache itself. Words are not things: I neither sit in the word ‘chair’ nor eat the word ‘food.’