•  53
    A Clone by any Other Name
    Journal of Philosophical Research 32 (9999): 247-255. 2007.
    The possibility of cloning human beings raises the difficult question: Which human lives have value and deserve legal protection? Current cloning legislation tries to hide the problem by illegitimately renaming the entities and processes in question. The Delaware cloning bill, (SB55 2003/2004) for example, permits and protects the creation of human embryos by cloning, as long as they will be destroyed for research and therapeutic purposes, but it adopts terminology which renders its import uncle…Read more
  •  36
    Libertarianism in Kane and Anselm
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 81 279-290. 2007.
    Anselm of Canterbury is the first Christian philosopher, perhaps the first philosopher, to offer a systematic analysis of libertarian freedom. His work prefigures that of Robert Kane, and looking at the two philosophers together is helpful in understanding and appreciating the work of each of them. In this paper I show how Anselm adopts a view of choice that foreshadows Kane’s doctrine of ‘plural voluntary control.’ Kane proposes this doctrine as an attempt to answer the ‘luck’ problem. Alfred M…Read more
  •  66
    A Defense of Anselm’s Cur Deus Homo Argument
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 74 187-200. 2000.
  •  75
  •  47
    Does God Cause Sin?
    Faith and Philosophy 20 (3): 371-378. 2003.
  •  133
    St. Augustine on Time and Eternity
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 70 (2): 207-223. 1996.
  •  110
    Omniscience, Eternity, and Freedom
    International Philosophical Quarterly 36 (4): 399-412. 1996.
  •  53
    The Abolition of Sin
    Faith and Philosophy 19 (1): 69-84. 2002.
  •  98
    Evidence for God from Certainty
    Faith and Philosophy 25 (1): 31-46. 2008.
    Human beings can have “strongly certain” beliefs—indubitable, veridical beliefs with a unique phenomenology—about necessarily true propositions like 2+2=4. On the plausible assumption that mathematical entities are platonic abstracta, naturalist theories fail to provide an adequate causal explanation for such beliefs because they cannot show how the propositional content of the causally inert abstracta can figure in a chain of physical causes. Theories which explain such beliefs as “correspondin…Read more
  •  195
    Anselmian Eternalism
    Faith and Philosophy 24 (1): 3-27. 2007.
    Anselm holds that God is timeless, time is tenseless, and humans have libertarian freedom. This combination of commitments is largely undefended incontemporary philosophy of religion. Here I explain Anselmian eternalism with its entailment of tenseless time, offer reasons for accepting it, and defend it against criticisms from William Hasker and other Open Theists. I argue that the tenseless view is coherent, that God’s eternal omniscience is consistent with libertarian freedom, that being etern…Read more
  •  75
    Hume on Necessary Causal Connections
    Philosophy 66 (258). 1991.
    According to David Hume our idea of a necessary connection between what we call cause and effect is produced when repeated observation of the conjunction of two events determines the mind to consider one upon the appearance of the other. No matter how we interpret Hume's theory of causation this explanation of the genesis of the idea of necessity is fraught with difficulty. I hope to show, looking at the three major interpretations of Hume's causal theory, that his account is contradictory, plai…Read more
  •  1
    Incarnation
    In Charles Taliaferro & Chad Meister (eds.), The Cambridge companion to Christian philosophical theology, Cambridge University Press. 2010.
  •  164
    Anselmian Eternalism
    Faith and Philosophy 24 (1): 3-27. 2007.
    Anselm holds that God is timeless, time is tenseless, and humans have libertarian freedom. This combination of commitments is largely undefended incontemporary philosophy of religion. Here I explain Anselmian eternalism with its entailment of tenseless time, offer reasons for accepting it, and defend it against criticisms from William Hasker and other Open Theists. I argue that the tenseless view is coherent, that God’s eternal omniscience is consistent with libertarian freedom, that being etern…Read more
  •  144
    God is Not the Author of Sin
    Faith and Philosophy 24 (3): 300-310. 2007.
    Following Anselm of Canterbury I argue against Hugh McCann’s claim that a traditional, classical theist understanding of God’s relationship to creation entails that God is the cause of our choices, including our choice to sin. I explain Anselm’s thesis that God causes all that has ontological status, yet does not cause sin. Then I show that McCann’s God, if not a sinner, must nonetheless be an unloving deceiver, McCann’s theodicy fails on its own terms, his proposed requirements for moral authen…Read more
  •  31
    The medieval approach to aardvarks, escalators, and God
    Journal of Value Inquiry 27 (1): 63-68. 1993.
  •  127
    Augustine's compatibilism
    Religious Studies 40 (4): 415-435. 2004.
    In analysing Augustine's views on freedom it is standard to draw two distinctions; one between an earlier emphasis on human freedom and a later insistence that God alone governs human destiny, and another between pre-lapsarian and post-lapsarian freedom. These distinctions are real and important, but underlying them is a more fundamental consistency. Augustine is a compatibilist from his earliest work on freedom through his final anti-Pelagian writings, and the freedom possessed by the un-fallen…Read more
  •  139
    It is often argued that the eternalist solution to the freedom/foreknowledge dilemma fails. If God's knowledge of your choices is eternally fixed, your choices are necessary and cannot be free. Anselm of Canterbury proposes an eternalist view which entails that all of time is equally real and truly present to God. God's knowledge of your choices entails only a ‘consequent’ necessity which does not conflict with libertarian freedom. I argue this by showing that if consequent necessity does confli…Read more
  •  97
  •  441
    God and Moral Realism
    International Philosophical Quarterly 45 (1): 103-118. 2005.
    Only God, or a very god-like being, can provide both the objectivity and the normative power necessary for a really robust moral realism. Further, I argue that the classical theist position—the view of Augustine, Anselm, and Aquinas—that morality is grounded in the nature of God, supplies a better metaphysical background for a strong moral realism than Divine Command Theory does. I respond briefly to the criticism that belief in God can have no positive role to play in solving ethical problems, …Read more
  •  71
    Defending Boethius: Two Case Studies in Charitable Interpretation
    International Philosophical Quarterly 51 (2): 241-257. 2011.
    Among those who study medieval philosophy there is a divide between historians and philosophers. Sometimes the historians chide the philosophers for failing to appreciate the historical factors at work in understanding a text, a philosopher, a school, or a system. But sometimes the philosopher may justly criticize the historian for failing to engage the past philosopher adequately as a philosopher. Here I defend a philosophically charitable methodology and offer two examples, taken from John Mar…Read more
  •  156
    Back to Eternalism
    Faith and Philosophy 26 (3): 320-338. 2009.
    Against my interpretation, Brian Leftow argues that Anselm of Canterbury held a presentist theory of time, and that presentism can be reconciled with Anselm’s commitments concerning divine omnipotence and omniscience. I respond, focusing mainly on two issues. First, it is difficult to understand the presentist theory which Leftow attributes to Anselm. I articulate my puzzlement in a way that I hope moves the discussion forward. Second, Leftow’s examples to demonstrate that presentism can be reco…Read more
  •  7
    Defending Boethius: Two Case Studies in Charitable Interpretation
    International Philosophical Quarterly 51 (2): 241-257. 2011.
    Among those who study medieval philosophy there is a divide between historians and philosophers. Sometimes the historians chide the philosophers for failing to appreciate the historical factors at work in understanding a text, a philosopher, a school, or a system. But sometimes the philosopher may justly criticize the historian for failing to engage the past philosopher adequately as a philosopher. Here I defend a philosophically charitable methodology and offer two examples, taken from John Mar…Read more
  •  21
    Back to Eternalism
    Faith and Philosophy 26 (3): 320-338. 2009.
    Against my interpretation, Brian Leftow argues that Anselm of Canterbury held a presentist theory of time, and that presentism can be reconciled with Anselm’s commitments concerning divine omnipotence and omniscience. I respond, focusing mainly on two issues. First, it is difficult to understand the presentist theory which Leftow attributes to Anselm. I articulate my puzzlement in a way that I hope moves the discussion forward. Second, Leftow’s examples to demonstrate that presentism can be reco…Read more