•  31
    Common sense and "relevance"
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 24 (1): 41-53. 1983.
  •  312
    On a derivation of the necessity of identity
    Synthese 191 (7): 1-19. 2014.
    The source, status, and significance of the derivation of the necessity of identity at the beginning of Kripke’s lecture “Identity and Necessity” is discussed from a logical, philosophical, and historical point of view
  •  117
    Truth
    Princeton University Press. 2011.
    This is a concise, advanced introduction to current philosophical debates about truth. A blend of philosophical and technical material, the book is organized around, but not limited to, the tendency known as deflationism, according to which there is not much to say about the nature of truth. In clear language, Burgess and Burgess cover a wide range of issues, including the nature of truth, the status of truth-value gaps, the relationship between truth and meaning, relativism and pluralism about …Read more
  •  20
    Adapated from talks at the UCLA Logic Center and the Pitt Philosophy of Science Series. Exposition of material from Fixing Frege, Chapter 2 (on predicative versions of Frege’s system) and from “Protocol Sentences for Lite Logicism” (on a form of mathematical instrumentalism), suggesting a connection. Provisional version: references remain to be added. To appear in Mathematics, Modality, and Models: Selected Philosophical Papers, coming from Cambridge University Press.
  •  160
    What is the simplest and most natural axiomatic replacement for the set-theoretic definition of the minimal fixed point on the Kleene scheme in Kripke’s theory of truth? What is the simplest and most natural set of axioms and rules for truth whose adoption by a subject who had never heard the word "true" before would give that subject an understanding of truth for which the minimal fixed point on the Kleene scheme would be a good model? Several axiomatic systems, old and new, are examined and ev…Read more
  •  18
    Review: C. L. Hamblin, The Modal "Probably." (review)
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (4): 582-583. 1970.
  •  213
    Philosophical Logic
    Princeton University Press. 2009.
    Philosophical Logic is a clear and concise critical survey of nonclassical logics of philosophical interest written by one of the world's leading authorities on the subject. After giving an overview of classical logic, John Burgess introduces five central branches of nonclassical logic, focusing on the sometimes problematic relationship between formal apparatus and intuitive motivation. Requiring minimal background and arranged to make the more technical material optional, the book offers a choi…Read more
  •  70
    Relevance: a fallacy?
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 22 (2): 97-104. 1981.
  •  41
    Abstract Objects
    Philosophical Review 101 (2): 414. 1992.
  •  33
    Axioms for tense logic. I. "Since" and "until"
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23 (4): 367-374. 1982.
  •  121
  •  20
    Saul Kripke has been a major influence on analytic philosophy and allied fields for a half-century and more. His early masterpiece, Naming and Necessity, reversed the pattern of two centuries of philosophizing about the necessary and the contingent. Although much of his work remains unpublished, several major essays have now appeared in print, most recently in his long-awaited collection Philosophical Troubles. In this book Kripke’s long-time colleague, the logician and philosopher John P. Burge…Read more
  •  48
    How Foundational Work in Mathematics Can Be Relevant to Philosophy of Science
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992. 1992.
    Foundational work in mathematics by some of the other participants in the symposium helps towards answering the question whether a heterodox mathematics could in principle be used as successfully as is orthodox mathematics in scientific applications. This question is turn, it will be argued, is relevant to the question how far current science is the way it is because the world is the way it is, and how far because we are the way we are, which is a central question, if not the central question, o…Read more
  •  77
    Decidability for branching time
    Studia Logica 39 (2-3): 203-218. 1980.
    The species of indeterminist tense logic called Peircean by A. N. Prior is proved to be recursively decidable
  •  120
    Quinus ab Omni Nævo Vindicatus
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (sup1): 25-65. 1997.
    Today there appears to be a widespread impression that W. V. Quine's notorious critique of modal logic, based on certain ideas about reference, has been successfully answered. As one writer put it some years ago: “His objections have been dead for a while, even though they have not yet been completely buried.” What is supposed to have killed off the critique? Some would cite the development of a new ‘possible-worlds’ model theory for modal logics in the 1960s; others, the development of new ‘dir…Read more
  •  195
    Why I am not a nominalist
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 24 (1): 93-105. 1983.
  •  42
    Beyond tense logic (review)
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 13 (3): 235-248. 1984.
  •  98
    Dummett's case for intuitionism
    History and Philosophy of Logic 5 (2): 177-194. 1984.
    Dummett's case against platonism rests on arguments concerning the acquisition and manifestation of knowledge of meaning. Dummett's arguments are here criticized from a viewpoint less Davidsonian than Chomskian. Dummett's case against formalism is obscure because in its prescriptive considerations are not clearly separated from descriptive. Dummett's implicit value judgments are here made explicit and questioned. ?Combat Revisionism!? Chairman Mao
  •  23
    On the Hanf number of souslin logic
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (3): 568-571. 1978.
    We show it is consistent with ZFC that the Hanf number of Ellentuck's Souslin logic should be exactly $\beth_{\omega_2}$
  •  128
    The Development of Modern Logic
    History and Philosophy of Logic 32 (2). 2011.
    History and Philosophy of Logic, Volume 32, Issue 2, Page 187-191, May 2011
  •  148
    Logic and time
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (4): 566-582. 1979.
  •  38
    Rigor and Structure
    Oxford University Press UK. 2015.
    While we are commonly told that the distinctive method of mathematics is rigorous proof, and that the special topic of mathematics is abstract structure, there has been no agreement among mathematicians, logicians, or philosophers as to just what either of these assertions means. John P. Burgess clarifies the nature of mathematical rigor and of mathematical structure, and above all of the relation between the two, taking into account some of the latest developments in mathematics, including the …Read more
  •  73
    Fixing Frege
    Princeton University Press. 2005.
    This book surveys the assortment of methods put forth for fixing Frege's system, in an attempt to determine just how much of mathematics can be reconstructed in ...
  •  10
    Review: Discussion: Soames on Empiricism (review)
    Philosophical Studies 129 (3). 2006.
  •  9
    Chapter Six. Intuitionistic Logic
    In J. W. Davis (ed.), Philosophical logic, D. Reidel. pp. 121-142. 1969.
  •  43
    Philosophy of Mathematics in the Twentieth Century: Selected Essays
    History and Philosophy of Logic 36 (1): 93-95. 2015.
    The second volume of Charles Parsons’ selected papers, dedicated to Solomon Feferman, Wilfred Sieg, and William Tait, collects eleven mainly historical essays and reviews on philosophy and philosop...
  •  24
    Read on relevance: a rejoinder
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 25 (3): 217-223. 1984.