• No title available: Religious studies
    Religious Studies 32 (3): 415-417. 1996.
  •  27
    Identity's crisis
    Philosophical Studies 53 (2). 1988.
  •  30
    History and the Brewmaster's Nose
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (2). 1985.
    A good historian often can assess the relative likelihood of competing historical claims more reliably on implicit grounds - intuitively, if you like - than in any other available way. This idea has been a persistent theme of Verstehen-theorists. It is, in essence, the old saw that there is no substitute for the brewmaster's nose, adapted to the art of producing historical brew. If true, it augments the importance of the historian relative to that of his arguments, and thereby gives him a dignit…Read more
  •  14
    The Kinds of Things: A Theory of Personal Identity Based on Transcendental Argument
    Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 62 (1): 240-243. 1996.
  •  23
    By speaking directly to the students in a personal tone, this text invites students to get excited about philosophy and to explore how philosophy affects them. Fourteen lively chapters take students deep into the world of philosophical thinking and challenge them to ponder life's big questions.
  •  163
    What really matters
    Synthese 162 (3). 2008.
    What really matters fundamentally in survival? That question—the one on which I focus—is not about what should matter or about metaphysics. Rather, it is a factual question the answer to which can be determined, if at all, only empirically. I argue that the answer to it is that in the case of many people it is not one’s own persistence, but continuing in ways that may involve one’s own cessation that really matters fundamentally in survival. Call this the surprising result. What are we to make o…Read more
  •  81
    “You have to begin to lose your memory, if only in bits and pieces, to realize that memory is what makes our lives. Life without memory is no life at all, . . . Our memory is our coherence, our reason, our feeling, even our action. Without it, we are nothing.” – Luis Buñuel..
  •  52
    This book traces the development of theories of the self and personal identity from the ancient Greeks to the present day. From Plato and Aristotle to Freud and Foucault, Raymond Martin and John Barresi explore the works of a wide range of thinkers and reveal the larger intellectual trends, controversies, and ideas that have revolutionized the way we think about ourselves. The authors open with ancient Greece, where the ideas of Plato, Aristotle, and the materialistic atomists laid the groundwor…Read more
  •  35
    Review (review)
    with Joan Scott and Cushing Strout
    History and Theory 34 (4): 320-339. 1995.
    In this extraordinarily rich and provocative book by an eminent intellectual historian and philosopher, Richard Sorabji argues persuasively that there was “an intense preoccupation” among ancient western thinkers with self and related notions. In the process, he provides fresh translations and often novel interpretations of the most important passages relevant to this contention in a host of thinkers, including Homer, Epicharmus, Heraclitus, Plato, Aristotle, Epicurus, Chrysippus, Cicero, Lucret…Read more
  •  107
    Survival of bodily death: A question of values: Raymond Martin
    Religious Studies 28 (2): 165-184. 1992.
    Does anyone ever survive his or her bodily death ? Could anyone? No speculative questions are older than these, or have been answered more frequently or more variously. None have been laid to rest more often, or — in our times — with more claimed decisiveness. Jay Rosenberg, for instance, no doubt speaks for many contemporary philosophers when he claims, in his recent book, to have ‘ demonstrated ’ that ‘ we cannot [even] make coherent sense of the supposed possibility that a person's history mi…Read more
  •  43
    Self-interest and survival
    American Philosophical Quarterly 29 (4): 319-30. 1992.
  •  99
    Self-concern from Priestley to Hazlitt
    with John Barresi
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 11 (3). 2003.
    himself or a proper object of his egoistic self-concern. Hazlitt concluded that belief in personal identity must be an acquired imaginary conception and that since in reality each of us is no more related to his or her future self than to the future self of any other person none of us is 2 ‘
  •  64
    This book is a major contribution to the philosophical literature on the nature of the self, personal identity and survival. Its distinctive methodology is one that is phenomenologically descriptive rather than metaphysical and normative. On the basis of this approach Raymond Martin shows that the distinction between self and other is not nearly as fundamental a feature of our so-called egoistic values as has been traditionally thought. He explains how the belief in a self as a fixed, continuous…Read more
  •  30
    Singular causal explanations
    Theory and Decision 2 (3): 221-237. 1972.
  •  26
    Self-Concern
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (3): 718-720. 2000.
  •  3
    Personal identity and what mattes in survival: An historical overview
    with J. Barresi
    In Raymond Martin & John Barresi (eds.), Personal Identity, Blackwell. pp. 1--74. 2003.
  •  10
    Personal Identity (edited book)
    with John Barnes
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2002.
  •  38
    It fills an important gap in intellectual history by being the first book to emphasize the enormous intellectual transformation in the eighteenth century, when...
  •  104
    Memory, connecting, and what matters in survival
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65 (1): 82-97. 1987.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  229
    Personal identity (edited book)
    with John Barresi
    Blackwell. 2003.
    These are the very scholars that were involved in initiating the revolution in personal identity theory.