•  101
    Basic reasons and first philosophy: A coherentist view of reasons
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (1): 75-93. 2012.
    This paper develops and defends a coherentist account of reasons. I develop three core ideas for this defense: a distinction between basic reasons and noninferential justification, the plausibility of the neglected argument against first philosophy, and an emergent account of reasons. These three ideas form the backbone for a credible coherentist view of reasons. I work toward this account by formulating and explaining the basic reasons dilemma. This dilemma reveals a wavering attitude that cohe…Read more
  •  57
    Reason and Explanation
    Palgrave Macmillan. 2014.
    Reason and Explanation develops a new explanationist account of epistemic justification. Poston argues that the explanatory virtues provide a plausible account of necessary and sufficient conditions for justification. The justification of a subject's belief consists in the explanatory virtue of her entire beliefs compared with other sets of beliefs she could have. Poston's argument for coherentism involves a defense of the epistemic value of background beliefs, the development of a novel fram…Read more
  •  27
    Richard Swinburne, Mind, Brain, & Free Will (review)
    Journal of Analytic Theology 4 480-484. 2016.
    _ _.
  •  78
    Justification without Awareness (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (2): 570-573. 2008.
    No Abstract
  •  102
    Foundational Evidentialism and the Problem of Scatter
    Abstracta 3 (2): 89-106. 2007.
    This paper addresses the scatter problem for foundational evidentialism. Reflection on the scatter problem uncovers significant epistemological lessons. The scatter problem is evaluated in connection with Ernest Sosa’s use of the problem as an argument against foundational evidentialism. Sosa’s strategy is to consider a strong intuition in favor of internalism—the new evil demon problem, and then illustrate how a foundational evidentialist account of the new evil demon problem succumbs to the sc…Read more
  •  96
    Skeptics without borders
    American Philosophical Quarterly 47 (3): 223. 2010.
    Timothy Williamson’s anti luminosity argument has received considerable attention. Escaping unnoticed, though, is a strikingly similar argument from David Hume. This paper highlights some of the arresting parallels between Williamson’s reasoning and Hume’s that will allow us to appreciate more deeply the plausibility of Williamson’s reasoning and to understand how, following Hume, we can extend this reasoning to undermine the “luminosity” of simple necessary truths. More broadly the parallels he…Read more
  •  44
    Nicholas Rescher: Common-Sense (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 24 (3): 361-363. 2007.
  •  55
    Introduction: “Epistemic coherentism”
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (1): 1-4. 2012.
  •  327
    Divine Hiddenness and the Nature of Belief
    Religious Studies 43 (2). 2007.
    In this paper we argue that attention to the intricacies relating to belief illustrate crucial difficulties with Schellenberg's hiddenness argument. This issue has been only tangentially discussed in the literature to date. Yet we judge this aspect of Schellenberg's argument deeply significant. We claim that focus on the nature of belief manifests a central flaw in the hiddenness argument. Additionally, attention to doxastic subtleties provides important lessons about the nature of faith
  •  383
    A user's guide to design arguments
    Religious Studies 44 (1): 99-110. 2008.
    We argue that there is a tension between two types of design arguments-the fine-tuning argument (FTA) and the biological design argument (BDA). The tension arises because the strength of each argument is inversely proportional to the value of a certain currently unknown probability. Since the value of that probability is currently unknown, we investigate the properties of the FTA and BDA on different hypothetical values of this probability. If our central claim is correct this suggests three res…Read more
  •  128
    Similarity and acquaintance: a dilemma
    Philosophical Studies 147 (3): 369-378. 2010.
    There is an interesting and instructive problem with Richard Fumerton's acquaintance theory of noninferential justification. Fumerton's explicit account requires acquaintance with the truth-maker of one's belief and yet he admits that one can have noninferential justification when one is not acquainted with the truthmaker of one's belief but instead acquainted with a very similar truth-maker. On the face of it this problem calls for clarification. However, there are skeptical issues lurking in t…Read more
  •  119
    Know How to Transmit Knowledge?
    Noûs 50 (4): 865-878. 2015.
    Intellectualism about knowledge-how is the view that practical knowledge is a species of propositional knowledge. I argue that this view is undermined by a difference in properties between knowledge-how and both knowledge-that and knowledge-wh. More specifically, I argue that both knowledge-that and knowledge-wh are easily transmitted via testimony while knowledge-how is not easily transmitted by testimony. This points to a crucial difference in states of knowledge. I also consider Jason Stanley…Read more
  •  64
    Finite Reasons Without Foundations
    Metaphilosophy 45 (2): 182-191. 2014.
    This article develops a theory of reasons that has strong similarities to Peter Klein's infinitism. The view it develops, Framework Reasons, upholds Klein's principles of avoiding arbitrariness (PAA) and avoiding circularity (PAC) without requiring an infinite regress of reasons. A view of reasons that holds that the “reason for” relation is constrained by PAA and that PAC can avoid an infinite regress if the “reason for” relation is contextual. Moreover, such a view of reasons can maintain that…Read more