•  287
    Knowing full well: the normativity of beliefs as performances
    Philosophical Studies 142 (1): 5-15. 2009.
    Belief is considered a kind of performance, which attains one level of success if it is true (or accurate), a second level if competent (or adroit), and a third if true because competent (or apt). Knowledge on one level (the animal level) is apt belief. The epistemic normativity constitutive of such knowledge is thus a kind of performance normativity. A problem is posed for this account by the fact that suspension of belief seems to fall under the same sort of epistemic normativity as does belie…Read more
  •  97
    Boghossian’s Fear of Knowledge (review)
    Philosophical Studies 141 (3). 2008.
  •  839
    Reflective knowledge in the best circles
    Journal of Philosophy 94 (8): 410-430. 1997.
    According to Moore, his argument meets three conditions for being a proof: first, the premiss is different from the conclusion; second, he knows the premiss to be the case; and, third, the conclusion follows deductively.2 Further conditions may be required, but he evidently thinks his proof would satisfy these as well. As Moore is well aware, many philosophers will feel he has not given “...any satisfactory proof of the point in question."3 Some, he believes, will want the premiss itself proved.…Read more
  •  165
    Privileged access
    In Aleksandar Jokic & Quentin Smith (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives, Oxford University Press. pp. 238-251. 2002.
    In Quentin Smith and Aleksander Jokic (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Essays (OUP, 2002).
  • Response
    In John Greco (ed.), Ernest Sosa: And His Critics, Oxford: Blackwell. 2004.
  •  68
    Internal Foundations or Eaternal Virtues?
    Philosophical Studies 131 (3): 761-773. 2006.
  •  29
    A Rejoinder on Actions and De Re Belief
    with Mark Pastin
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11 (4). 1981.
    Richard Feldman in ‘Actions and De Re Beliefs’ attacks ‘latitudinarian’ accounts of de re belief in terms of de dicta belief, including those defended in print by one or the other of us. Feldman's case against latitudinarian views rests on the claim that such accounts do not allow de re attitudes an explanatory role they obviously can fulfil.
  •  56
    Boghossian’s F ear of Knowledge (review)
    Philosophical Studies 141 (3). 2008.
  •  65
    On Metaphysical Analysis
    Journal of Philosophical Research 40 (Supplement): 309-314. 2015.
    What follows offers a solution for the problem of causal deviance in its three varieties. We consider Davidson on action, Grice on perception, and the account of knowledge as apt belief, as belief that gets it right through competence rather than luck. We take up the opposition between such traditional accounts and “disjunctivist” alternatives. And we explore how our take on the point and substance of metaphysical analysis bears on the problem and on competing reactions to it.
  •  274
    Epistemic Agency
    Journal of Philosophy 110 (11): 585-605. 2013.
  •  265
  • Philosophical Scepticism
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 68 263-307. 1994.
  •  78
    Imagery and Imagination
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 25 (1): 485-499. 1985.
    1. Sensa and propositional experience. 2. An option between propositions and properties (as objects or contents of sensory experience). 3. The property option and adverbialism. 4. Sensa as images, images as intentionalia. 5. Do we refer directly to sensa? 6. Focusing and the supervenience of images and our reference to them: a question raised. 7. Internal and external properties of images and characters. Strict vistas introduced. 8. A correction on strict vistas. 9. Focusing and experience: the …Read more
  •  1250
    The place of reasons in epistemology
    In Daniel Star (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity, Oxford University Press. 2018.
    This paper considers the place of reasons in the metaphysics of epistemic normativity and defends a middle ground between two popular extremes in the literature. Against members of the ‘reasons first’ movement, we argue that reasons are not the sole fundamental constituents of epistemic normativity. We suggest instead that the virtue-theoretic property of competence is the key building block. To support this approach, we note that reasons must be possessed to play a role in the analysis of ce…Read more
  •  6
    Metaphysics: An Anthology, 1st Edition (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 1999.
    Thoroughly updated, the second edition of this highly successful textbook continues to represent the most comprehensive and authoritative collection of canonical readings in metaphysics. In addition to updated material from the first edition, it presents entirely new sections on ontology and the metaphysics of material objects. One of the most comprehensive and authoritative metaphysics anthologies available - now updated and expanded Offers the most important contemporary works on the central i…Read more
  •  137
  •  111
    Human knowledge, animal and reflective
    Philosophical Studies 106 (3). 2001.
    Stephen Grimm finds me inclined to bifurcate epistemic assessment into higher and lower orders while showing awareness of this only in recent writings. Two untoward consequences allegedly follow: (a) my rejection of Virtue Reliabilism, and (b) my knowledge-based account of the value attaching to our knowledge on the higher level. By contrast, Grimm considers Virtue Reliabilism a perfectly adequate account of knowledge, while the higher epistemic state he believes to be, rather, understanding, wh…Read more
  •  67
    The truth of modest realism
    Philosophical Issues 3 177-195. 1993.
    True, the believing could not in those cir- cumstances be there the object of belief being there. accept a notion of correspondence or reference according to which a word or a brain state of ours can refer to some external or or independent (This no more forces
  •  28
    Presuppositions of Empirical Knowledge
    Philosophical Papers 15 (2-3): 75-87. 1986.
    No abstract
  •  15
    Minimal Intuition
    In Michael DePaul & William Ramsey (eds.), Rethinking Intuition, Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 257-269. 1998.
  •  86
    Responses to Nuccetelli, Lemos, and Bueno
    Metaphilosophy 40 (2): 203-213. 2009.
    Abstract: Susana Nuccetelli discusses critically my account of Moore's Proof of the External World. Noah Lemos takes up my views on skepticism and my distinction between animal knowledge and reflective knowledge. Otávio Bueno focuses on my treatment of dream skepticism. In this article I offer replies to my three critics.
  •  13
    Précis of A Virtue Epistemology
    Philosophical Studies 143 (3): 395-395. 2009.
  •  74
    Fregean reference defended
    Philosophical Issues 6 91-99. 1995.
    What is involved in acquiring a russellian proposition (x, φ) as content of an attitude: what does it take for one to acquire such an attitude de re? How do we gain access to x itself so as to be able to have (x, φ) as content of our thought?
  •  1773
    The Epistemology of Disagreement
    In Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Social Epistemology, Oxford University Press. 2010.
  • Condition
    In Audi Robert (ed.), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press. pp. 149. 1995.