•  50
    Moral Relativism, Cognitivism and Defeasible Rules
    Social Philosophy and Policy 11 (1): 116-138. 1994.
    Naturalism rejects a sui generis and fundamental realm of the evaluative or normative. Thought and talk about the good and the right must hence be understood without appeal to any such evaluative or normative concepts or properties. In Sections I and II, we see noncognitivism step forward with its account of evaluative and normative language as fundamentally optative or prescriptive. Prescriptivism falls afoul of several problems. Prominent among them below is the “problem of prima facie reasons…Read more
  •  18
    Vincent A. Tomas 1916-1995
    with John Ladd
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 69 (5). 1996.
  •  23
    The Semantics of Imperatives
    American Philosophical Quarterly 4 (1). 1967.
  •  11
    Essays on the Philosophy of George Berkeley (edited book)
    D. Reidel. 1986.
    A tercentenary conference of March, 1985, drew to Newport, Rhode Island, nearly all the most distinguished Berkeley scholars now active. The conference was organized by the International Berkeley Society, with the support of several institutions and many people. This volume represents a selection of the lead papers deliv ered at that conference, most now revised. The Cartesian marriage of Mind and Body has proved an uneasy union. Each side has claimed supremacy and usurped the rights of the othe…Read more
  •  12
    External realism and philosophy in transition
    Journal of Social Philosophy 22 (1): 183-186. 1991.
    This paper was written for a panel session, in which I was asked to represent an analytic perspective. On reflection I found that there is no such thing, however, and that what best unifies the analytic traditions is not even a set of questions, much less a set of answers, but only agreement on certain standards of clarity and argumentation, and an interest in dialectic and debate. Certain issues have long dominated the analytic agenda, it is true, and I see no better way to represent an analyti…Read more
  • A Companion to Epitemology (edited book)
    Blackwell. 1992.
  •  189
    Metaphysics: An Anthology, 2nd Edition (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2011.
    Thoroughly updated, the second edition of this highly successful textbook continues to represent the most comprehensive and authoritative collection of canonical readings in metaphysics. In addition to updated material from the first edition, it presents entirely new sections on ontology and the metaphysics of material objects.
  • Philosophical Issues, Philosophy of Language (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2007.
    Some of the most distinguished active contributors to the field join together for a collection of their most recent work. Brings together important new papers by many of the most distinguished philosophers of language Takes up some of the central issues in the field in recent years Includes some of the best cutting-edge work in philosophy of language
  •  46
  •  149
    Goldman’s Reliabilism and Virtue Epistemology
    Philosophical Topics 29 (1-2): 383-400. 2001.
  •  43
    Essays on the philosophy of Roderick M. Chisholm (edited book)
    with Roderick M. Chisholm
    Rodopi. 1979.
  • Knowledge of self, others, and world
    In Kirk Ludwig (ed.), Donald Davidson, Cambridge University Press. pp. 2003--163. 2003.
  •  93
    Replies to commentators on A Virtue Epistemology
    Philosophical Studies 144 (1): 137-147. 2009.
    Paul Boghossian discusses critically my account of intuition as a source of epistemic status. Stewart Cohen takes up my views on skepticism, on dreams, and on epistemic competence and competences and their relation to human knowledge. Hilary Kornblith focuses on my animal/reflective distinction, and, along with Cohen, on my comparison between how dreams might mislead us and how other bad epistemic contexts can do so. In this paper I offer replies to my three critics.
  •  58
    Causation and conditionals (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 1975.
    Mackie, J. L. Causes and conditions.--Taylor, R. The metaphysics of causation.--Scriven, M. Defects of the necessary condition analysis of causation.--Kim, J. Causes and events: Mackie on causation.--Anscombe, G. E. M. Causality and determination.--Davidson, D. Causal relations.--Wright, G. H. von. On the logic and epistemology of the causal relation.--Ducasse, C. J. On the nature and the observability of the causal relation.--Sellars, W. S. Counterfactuals.--Chisholm, R. M. Law statements and c…Read more
  •  67
    Two conceptions of knowledge
    Journal of Philosophy 67 (3): 59-66. 1970.
    Knowledge of the nature of knowledge is deplorably scarce. Fortunately, the reason is not lack of interest. On the contrary, the bewildering variety of competing theories is part of the problem. It is to, be hoped, however, that intensive discussion of such theories will help reduce the scarcity. In what follows I want to contribute to this end by briefly discussing two of the theories.
  •  287
    Knowing full well: the normativity of beliefs as performances
    Philosophical Studies 142 (1): 5-15. 2009.
    Belief is considered a kind of performance, which attains one level of success if it is true (or accurate), a second level if competent (or adroit), and a third if true because competent (or apt). Knowledge on one level (the animal level) is apt belief. The epistemic normativity constitutive of such knowledge is thus a kind of performance normativity. A problem is posed for this account by the fact that suspension of belief seems to fall under the same sort of epistemic normativity as does belie…Read more
  •  839
    Reflective knowledge in the best circles
    Journal of Philosophy 94 (8): 410-430. 1997.
    According to Moore, his argument meets three conditions for being a proof: first, the premiss is different from the conclusion; second, he knows the premiss to be the case; and, third, the conclusion follows deductively.2 Further conditions may be required, but he evidently thinks his proof would satisfy these as well. As Moore is well aware, many philosophers will feel he has not given “...any satisfactory proof of the point in question."3 Some, he believes, will want the premiss itself proved.…Read more
  •  97
    Boghossian’s Fear of Knowledge (review)
    Philosophical Studies 141 (3). 2008.
  •  165
    Privileged access
    In Aleksandar Jokic & Quentin Smith (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives, Oxford University Press. pp. 238-251. 2002.
    In Quentin Smith and Aleksander Jokic (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Essays (OUP, 2002).
  •  265
  •  273
    Epistemic Agency
    Journal of Philosophy 110 (11): 585-605. 2013.
  • Response
    In John Greco (ed.), Ernest Sosa: And His Critics, Oxford: Blackwell. 2004.
  •  68
    Internal Foundations or Eaternal Virtues?
    Philosophical Studies 131 (3): 761-773. 2006.
  •  56
    Boghossian’s F ear of Knowledge (review)
    Philosophical Studies 141 (3). 2008.
  •  29
    A Rejoinder on Actions and De Re Belief
    with Mark Pastin
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11 (4). 1981.
    Richard Feldman in ‘Actions and De Re Beliefs’ attacks ‘latitudinarian’ accounts of de re belief in terms of de dicta belief, including those defended in print by one or the other of us. Feldman's case against latitudinarian views rests on the claim that such accounts do not allow de re attitudes an explanatory role they obviously can fulfil.
  •  65
    On Metaphysical Analysis
    Journal of Philosophical Research 40 (Supplement): 309-314. 2015.
    What follows offers a solution for the problem of causal deviance in its three varieties. We consider Davidson on action, Grice on perception, and the account of knowledge as apt belief, as belief that gets it right through competence rather than luck. We take up the opposition between such traditional accounts and “disjunctivist” alternatives. And we explore how our take on the point and substance of metaphysical analysis bears on the problem and on competing reactions to it.