•  12
    Experience and Foundationalism in Audi’s The Architecture of Reason (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (1). 2003.
    In The Architecture of Reason, Robert Audi claims that good reasoning always has some foundation in experience. It is not clear, however, precisely what kind of experience is supposed to ground practical reasoning. It is also not clear whether inference is necessary for a belief to be justified, even when the source of the belief is experience without inference. Finally, it is not clear why beliefs based on some kinds of experience would not need to be justified by inference when beliefs based o…Read more
  •  11
    Experience and Foundationalism in Audi's The Architecture of Reason (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (1): 181-187. 2003.
    Robert Audi’s The Architecture of Reason is a magnificent consolidation of decades of original work by a masterful philosopher. Its scope is impressive, as it covers both theoretical and practical reason in a slim volume. More impressive yet is its coherence, for Audi reveals a unified structure shared by what many philosophers assume to be disparate fields.
  •  69
    Do Psychopaths Refute Internalism?
    In Thomas Schramme (ed.), Being Amoral: Psychopathy and Moral Incapacity, Mit Press. pp. 187-208. 2014.
    The chapter focuses on the philosophical debate between moral motivational internalism and externalism. The author analyzes and thereby challenges the conceptual problems underlying this quarrel in relation to the apparent empirical findings on psychopathy. Major obstacles in making progress in this debate are conceptual and methodological problems. First, there is not a clear-cut and undisputed definition of moral internalism. Second, empirical results about a lack of moral judgment are not for…Read more
  •  4
    Brings together ten of the nation's finest and most provocative legal scholars to present their views on constitutional interpretation. All of these papers are very recent, and four were written especially for this volume.
  •  20
    Classy pyrrhonism
    In Pyrrhonian skepticism, Oxford University Press. pp. 188--207. 2004.
    This essay invokes a technical framework of contrast classes within which Pyrrhonians can accept knowledge claims that are relativized to specific contrast classes, but avoid all unrelativized knowledge claims and all presuppositions about which contrast classes are really relevant. Pyrrhonians can then assert part of the content of everyday knowledge claims without privileging the everyday perspective or any other perspective. This framework provides a precise way to understand the central clai…Read more
  • Coherentism
    In Moral skepticisms, Oxford University Press. 2006.
    This chapter explains moral coherentism as the view that some moral beliefs are justified by virtue of cohering with a system of belief that is coherent in the sense that it is consistent, connected, and comprehensive. Second-order beliefs about reliability are introduced to handle standard objections to coherentism. It concludes that coherence can make some moral beliefs justified out of a modest contrast class, but not out of an extreme contrast class with moral nihilism. This final chapter, t…Read more
  • Classy Moral Pyrrhonism
    In Moral skepticisms, Oxford University Press. 2006.
    This chapter applies the general epistemology in Chapter 5 to moral beliefs in particular, and discusses the relevance of moral nihilism. It presents a moderate classy Pyrrhonian moral skepticism, which claims that some moral beliefs can be justified out of a modest contrast class, but no moral beliefs can be justified out of an unlimited contrast class. Since neither contrast class is the relevant one, no moral belief is justified without qualification.
  • Are Moral Beliefs Truth‐Apt?
    In Moral skepticisms, Oxford University Press. 2006.
    This chapter discusses expressivism as a form of moral skepticism that denies the truth-aptness of moral beliefs and judgments. It focuses on whether expressivists can solve the problem of embedding by allowing that some moral beliefs have a minimal kind of truth, and whether expressivists can account for the apparent objectivity of moral beliefs. It concludes that if expressivists succeed in mimicking all apparently realistic moral language, then expressivism does not really matter to moral epi…Read more
  •  28
    For Goodness' Sake
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 83-91. 2003.
  •  261
    A Solution to Forrester's Paradox of Gentle Murder
    Journal of Philosophy 82 (3): 162-168. 1985.
  •  24
    Begging the question
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 (2). 1999.
    No topic in informal logic is more important than begging the question. Also, none is more subtle or complex. We cannot even begin to understand the fallacy of begging the question without getting clear about arguments, their purposes, and circularity. So I will discuss these preliminary topics first. This will clear the path to my own account of begging the question. Then I will anticipate some objections. Finally, I will apply my account to a well-known and popular response to scepticism by G.…Read more
  •  32
    Are moral judgments unified?
    with Thalia Wheatley
    Philosophical Psychology 27 (4): 451-474. 2014.
    Whenever psychologists, neuroscientists, or philosophers draw conclusions about moral judgments in general from a small selected sample, they assume that moral judgments are unified by some common and peculiar feature that enables generalizations and makes morality worthy of study as a unified field. We assess this assumption by considering the six main candidates for a unifying feature: content, phenomenology, force, form, function, and brain mechanisms. We conclude that moral judgment is not u…Read more
  •  19
    Moral Intuitions
    with Liane Young
    In John M. Doris (ed.), Moral Psychology Handbook, Oxford University Press. pp. 246-272. 2010.
  •  5
    An empirical challenge to moral intuitionism
    In Jill Graper Hernandez (ed.), The New Intuitionism, A&c Black. pp. 11--28. 2011.
  •  8
    A light theory of color
    with David Sparrow
    Philosophical Studies 110 (3): 267-284. 2002.
    Traditional theories locate color in primary qualities of objects, in dispositional properties of objects, in visual fields, or nowhere. In contrast, we argue that color is located in properties of light. More specifically, light is red iff there is a property P of the light that typically interacts with normal human perceivers to give the sensation of red. This is an error theory, because objects and visual fields that appear red are not really red, since they lack the properties that make ligh…Read more
  •  17
    A contrastivist manifesto
    Social Epistemology 22 (3). 2008.
    General contrastivism holds that all claims of reasons are relative to contrast classes. This approach applies to explanation (reasons why things happen), moral philosophy (reasons for action), and epistemology (reasons for belief), and it illuminates moral dilemmas, free will, and the grue paradox. In epistemology, contrast classes point toward an account of justified belief that is compatible with reliabilism and other externalisms. Contrast classes also provide a model for Pyrrhonian sceptici…Read more
  • Are Any Moral Beliefs True?
    In Moral skepticisms, Oxford University Press. 2006.
    This chapter explores moral nihilism and error theories, which hold that moral beliefs are truth-apt but never true. Arguments for such views from relativity, evolution, and epistemological, psychological, and metaphysical queerness are all explained and critically assessed. The logical and semantic coherence of moral nihilism is then defended. The result is that moral nihilism is far from proven, but remains a serious contender in moral epistemology.
  •  17
    A defense of modus ponens
    with James Moor and Robert Fogelin
    Journal of Philosophy 83 (5): 296-300. 1986.
  • Are Any Moral Beliefs Justified?
    In Moral skepticisms, Oxford University Press. 2006.
    This chapter distinguishes different ways for moral beliefs and believers to be justified: instrumentally or epistemically, permissively or positively, slightly or adequately, and personally or impersonally. It explains the two main arguments against justified moral belief: the skeptical regress argument and the skeptical hypothesis or scenario argument. It concludes that these arguments pose a dilemma because their flaws are hard to detect, and their conclusions are hard to believe.
  •  16
    A Defence of Modus Tollens
    with James Moor and Robert Fogelin
    Analysis 50 (1). 1990.
  •  5
    Abstract + concrete = paradox
    In Joshua Michael Knobe & Shaun Nichols (eds.), Experimental Philosophy, Oxford University Press. 2008.
  •  17
    A Defence Of Modus Tollens
    with Alonso Church
    Analysis 50 (1): 9. 1990.
  •  1
    An argument for descriptivism
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (2): 281-91. 1999.
  •  92
    Ideal for undergraduate courses in philosophy of law, this comprehensive anthology examines such topics as the concept of law, the dispute between natural law theorists and legal positivists, the relations between law and morality, criminal responsibility and legal punishment, the rights of the individual against the state, justice and equality, and legal evidence as compared with scientific evidence. The readings have been selected from both philosophy and law journals and include classic texts…Read more
  •  4
    Knobe cites both relevant alternatives and defaults on a continuum to explain how moral judgments influence intuitions about certain apparently non-moral notions. I ask (1) how these two accounts are related, (2) whether they exclude or supplement supposedly competing theories, and (3) how to get positive evidence that people consider relevant alternatives when applying such notions
  •  18
    An argument for consequentialism
    Philosophical Perspectives 6 399-421. 1992.