•  7
    The Phenomenological Motivation of the Later Heidegger
    Philosophy Today 53 (Supplement): 182-189. 2009.
  •  894
    Heidegger’s Distinction between Scientific and Philosophical Judgments
    Philosophy Today 51 (Supplement): 33-41. 2007.
    Some commentators, such as Jürgen Habermas, think Martin Heidegger is guilty of a performative contradiction, because he uses judgments to situate judgments in a non-judicative context. This paper defends Heidegger by distinguishing two senses of judgment in his thought. Temporality enables two different directions of inquiry and hence two kinds of judgment. Scientific judgments arise when we turn from the temporal horizon toward entities alone; phenomenological judgments arise when we return…Read more
  •  68
    Marcel and Heidegger on the Proper Matter and Manner of Thinking
    Philosophy Today 48 (1): 94-109. 2004.
    Both Gabriel Marcel and Martin Heidegger hold that the proper task of philosophy is to think mystery. This is not the unknown as such; rather it is what ever again gives rise to thought. For both philosophers, representational thinking is inadequate to this subject matter. The present study explicates their attempts to approach mystery and identifies their final difference. For Marcel, the domain of mystery is opened in interpersonal presence; for Heidegger, mystery is opened in the appropri…Read more
  •  1624
    Perceiving Other Animate Minds in Augustine
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 90 (1): 25-48. 2016.
    This paper dispels the Cartesian reading of Augustine’s treatment of mind and other minds by examining key passages from De Trinitate and De Civitate Dei. While Augustine does vigorously argue that mind is indubitable and immaterial, he disavows the fundamental thesis of the dualistic tradition: the separation of invisible spirit and visible body. The immediate self-awareness of mind includes awareness of life, that is, of animating a body. Each of us animates our own body; seeing other animated…Read more
  •  1430
    Augustinian Elements in Heidegger’s Philosophical Anthropology
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 78 263-275. 2004.
    Heidegger’s 1921 lecture course, “Augustine and Neo-Platonism,” shows the emergence of certain Augustinian elements in Heidegger’s account of the human being. In Book X of Augustine’s Confessions, Heidegger finds a rich account of the historicity and facticity of human existence. He interprets Augustinian molestia (facticity) by exhibiting the complex relation of curare (the fundamental character of factical life) and the three forms of tentatio (possibilities of falling). In this analysis, mole…Read more
  •  2555
    Heidegger and the Human Difference
    Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (1): 175-193. 2015.
    This paper provides a qualified defense of Martin Heidegger’s controversial assertion that humans and animals differ in kind, not just degree. He has good reasons to defend the human difference, and his thesis is compatible with the evolution of humans from other animals. He argues that the human environment is the world of meaning and truth, an environment which peculiarly makes possible truthful activities such as biology. But the ability to be open to truth cannot be a feature of human bio…Read more
  •  30
    The Wonder of Questioning
    Philosophy Today 49 (Supplement): 185-192. 2005.
  •  82
    Heidegger on overcoming rationalism through transcendental philosophy
    Continental Philosophy Review 41 (1): 17-41. 2007.
    Modernity is not only the culmination of the “oblivion of being,” for it also provides, in the form of transcendental thinking, a way to recover the original relation of thought to being. Heidegger develops this account through several lecture courses from 1935–1937, especially the 1935–1936 lecture course on Kant, and the account receives a kind of completion in the 1936–1938 manuscript, Contributions to Philosophy. Kant limits the dominance of rationalistic prejudices by reconnecting thought t…Read more
  •  81
    Teleology, Purpose, and Power in Nietzsche
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 84 (2): 413-426. 2010.
    Nietzsche subjects traditional philosophical causality to a skeptical critique. With the moderns, he rejects form as superficial. Against the moderns, he findsphysical laws and their ground in a free consciousness equally superficial, and he thinks that the principle of utility is ultimately life denying. However, Nietzscheis not a skeptic, and he has his own doctrine of causality centered on the noble power of the philosopher. The philosopher has the ability to impose new purposes, and this pow…Read more
  •  10
    Augustinian Elements in Heidegger’s Philosophical Anthropology
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 78 263-275. 2004.
    Heidegger’s 1921 lecture course, “Augustine and Neo-Platonism,” shows the emergence of certain Augustinian elements in Heidegger’s account of the humanbeing. In Book X of Augustine’s Confessions, Heidegger finds a rich account of the historicity and facticity of human existence. He interprets Augustinianmolestia (facticity) by exhibiting the complex relation of curare (the fundamental character of factical life) and the three forms of tentatio (possibilities of falling).In this analysis, molesti…Read more
  •  1265
    How Must We Be for the Resurrection to Be Good News?
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 89 245-261. 2015.
    While the promise of the resurrection appears wonderful, it is also perplexing: How can the person raised be one and the same person as the one that dies? And if the raised person is not the same, why should any of us mortals regard the promise of the resurrection as good news? In this paper, I articulate the part-whole structure of human nature that supports belief in the sameness of the resurrected person’s identity and the desirability of the resurrection: the immaterial core of the person mu…Read more
  •  1225
    Unmasking the Person
    International Philosophical Quarterly 50 (4): 447-460. 2010.
    By showing how the person appears, this paper calls into question the Cartesian prejudice that restricts appearance to objects. The paper recapitulates the origin of the term “person,” which originally designated the masks and characters donned by actors and only subsequently came to designate each particular human being. By concealing a face, the mask establishes a character who speaks with words of his own. The mask points to the face and to speech as ways the person appears. It belongs to the…Read more