•  1
    The historical development of the understanding of water is traced in the light of the development of the general concept of chemical substance. From the times of the earliest known ancient Greek philosophers, water has played a central role in the conception of the material constitution of the world. But it was Aristotle who developed the most sophisticated understanding of water to have come down to us from the ancients. He viewed it as part of an intricate and systematic theory of chemical su…Read more
  •  215
    Making Theorem-Proving in Modal Logic Easy
    In Lars-Göran Johansson, Jan Österberg & Rysiek Śliwiński (eds.), Logic, Ethics and All That Jazz: Essays in Honour of Jordan Howard Sobel, . pp. 187-202. 2009.
    A system for the modal logic K furnishes a simple mechanical process for proving theorems.
  • Chemistry, the science of substances and their transformations with roots in antiquity, provides as rich a source as any of the claims about what is not directly observable in the light of ideas reflecting both constancy and change. An important distinction in chemistry is that between macroscopic and microscopic realms, mistaken by positivists as a distinction between observable and theoretical and later by certain realists as a distinction between the merely superficial and the deeply theoreti…Read more
  • One Substance or More?
    In Lee McIntyre & Eric Scerri (eds.), Philosophy of Chemistry: Growth of a New Discipline, Springer. pp. 91-105. 2015.
    Chemistry builds on distinctions of substance, which presupposes that matter can be divided into substances and compared with other matter and itself on different occasions as being of the same substance. Even identifying a quantity of matter as comprising a single substance presupposes the same substance relation, it being a quantity all of whose spatial parts are the same substance. But criteria of purity have been important for isolating substances and investigating their characteristic prope…Read more
  • Aspects of the Concept of Potentiality in Chemistry
    with Robin Hendry
    In Kristina Engelhard & Michael Quante (eds.), Handbook of Potentiality, Springer. pp. 375-400. 2018.
  •  1
    Elements
    In Stamatios Gerogiorgakis, Johanna Seibt & Guido Imaguire (eds.), Handbook of Mereology, Philosophia. pp. 197-200. 2017.
  •  1
    Chemistry
    In Stamatios Gerogiorgakis, Johanna Seibt & Guido Imaguire (eds.), Handbook of Mereology, Philosophia. pp. 141-147. 2017.
  •  25
    Was Duhem Justified in not Distinguishing Between Physical and Chemical Atomism?
    Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science 2 108. 2017.
    Chemists in the late nineteenth century were apt to distinguish the theory of chemical structure they advocated as chemical, as opposed to physical, atomism. The failure on Duhem’s part to consider any such distinction in his critique of atomism might be taken to be a lacuna in his argument. Far from being a weakness in his stance, however, I argue that he had good systematic reasons for not taking such a distinction seriously.
  • Review of Keith Seddon, Time: A philosophical treatment (review)
    Theoria 54 (3): 220. 1988.
  •  46
    This book is about matter. It involves our ordinary concept of matter in so far as this deals with enduring continuants that stand in contrast to the occurrents or processes in which they are involved, and concerns the macroscopic realm of middle-sized objects of the kind familiar to us on the surface of the earth and their participation in medium term processes. The emphasis will be on what science rather than philosophical intuition tells us about the world, and on chemistry rather than the ph…Read more
  •  83
    This article is an overview of some of the contemporary debates in philosophy of chemistry. We discuss the nature of chemical substances, the individuation of chemical kinds, the relationship between chemistry and physics, and the nature of the chemical bond.
  •  10
    For Good Measure (edited book)
    with Jan Odelstad, Lars Lindahl, and Rysiek Sliwi Nski
    . 1997.
  •  99
    Philosophy of chemistry
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2011.
    Chemistry is the study of the structure and transformation of matter. When Aristotle founded the field in the 4th century BCE, his conceptual grasp of the nature of matter was tailored to accommodate a relatively simple range of observable phenomena. In the 21st century, chemistry has become the largest scientific discipline, producing over half a million publications a year ranging from direct empirical investigations to substantial theoretical work. However, the specialized interest in the con…Read more
  •  32
    Review of Stefano Bordoni, Taming Complexity: Duhem’s Third Pathway to Thermodynamcis, Editrice Montefeltro, Urbino, 2012.
  •  35
    The status of the chemical bond has long been a controversial issue with the increasing distance between quantum chemists’ theoretical understanding of molecular stability and the ideas of experimental chemists. Some aspects of the development of the concept of a hydrogen bond are discussed with a view to assessing its import on the general question.
  •  73
    When did atoms begin to do any explanatory work in chemistry?
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 18 (2 & 3). 2004.
    During the 19th century atomism was a controversial issue in chemistry. It is an oversimplification to dismiss the critics' arguments as all falling under the general positivist view that what can't be seen can't be. The more interesting lines of argument either questioned whether any coherent notion of an atom had ever been formulated or questioned whether atoms were ever really given any explanatory role. At what point, and for what reasons, did atomistic hypotheses begin to explain anything i…Read more
  •  17
    Substitution: Duhem’s Explication of a Chemical Paradigm
    Perspectives on Science 4 (4): 408-433. 1996.
    An exposition of Pierre Duhem’s formulation of the structure of chemical substances as expressed by their formulas is given, presenting it as a development of his essentially Aristotelian view of mixtures. Duhem’s masterly development of the subject displays an eye for logical clarity familiar from his work in thermodynamics but applied here to the extraction of what he regarded as true from the history of chemistry. Though no longer defensible, the account has a conceptual interest in its own r…Read more
  •  8
    The Phase Rule and the Notion of Substance
    In Henk W. de Regt (ed.), Epsa Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009, Springer. pp. 253--262. 2010.
    In response to difficulties in understanding the notion of chemical substance at issue in Gibbs’ phase rule, there is a long tradition of reformulating the simple statement of the rule. The leading idea is to rewrite the rule with a term for the number of substances actually present and to introduce additional terms making explicit the various kinds of restrictions which in the original formulation are taken to be incorporated into Gibbs’ notion of the number of independent substances. Although …Read more
  •  14
    Tense Logic (review)
    with L. Aqvist and F. Guenthner
    Philosophical Quarterly 29 (117): 372. 1979.
    Review of Tense Logic, ed. by Lennart Åqvist and Frans Guenthner,
  •  58
    Critical Notice: Times, Worlds and Selves (review)
    Synthese 40 (2): 389-408. 1979.
    Review of A. N. Prior and Kit Fine, Times, Worlds and Selves, Duckworth London, 1977.
  •  65
    The source of chemical bonding
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 45 1-13. 2014.
    Developments in the application of quantum mechanics to the understanding of the chemical bond are traced with a view to examining the evolving conception of the covalent bond. Beginning with the first quantum mechanical resolution of the apparent paradox in Lewis’s conception of a shared electron pair bond by Heitler and London, the ensuing account takes up the challenge molecular orbital theory seemed to pose to the classical conception of the bond. We will see that the threat of delocalisatio…Read more
  •  157
    Transient things and permanent stuff
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88 (1). 2010.
    A view of individuals as constituted of quantities of matter, both understood as continuants enduring over time, is elaborated in some detail. Constitution is a three-place relation which can't be collapsed to identity because of the place-holder for a time and because individuals and quantities of matter have such a radically different character. Individuals are transient entities with limited lifetimes, whereas quantities are permanent existents undergoing change in physical and chemical prope…Read more
  •  5
    Prima facie, there are two kinds of expression used in English to make reference to time: those involving explicit mention of time and temporal ordering relations, and tenses involving no such explicit reference. Taking as a criterion of adequacy the unification of both these aspects, a systematization is proposed (owing much to Reichenbach) which provides a characterization of tenses. The theory is not based on the notion of a proposition with variable truth value which formed the cornerstone o…Read more
  •  24
    Reduction in chemistry - a second response to Scerri
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14 (3). 2000.
    In this rejoinder to Eric Scerri's response to my first comment on his paper on the reduction of chemistry to physics, the main point concerns laws in chemistry. But other themes touched upon include the assumptions involved in ab initio calculations, the question of what is reduced to what on Scerri's view, and the significance he attaches to the term "naturalism".
  •  57
    Substance and Modality
    Philosophy of Science 73 (5): 829-840. 2006.
    The Aristotelian distinction between actual and potential presence of a substance in a mixture forms part of a conception of mixture which stands in contrast to atomist and Stoic theories as propounded by the ancients. But the central ideas on which these theories are built need not be combined and opposed to one another in precisely the ways envisaged by these ancient theories. This is well illustrated by Duhem, who maintained the Aristotelian idea that the original ingredients are only potenti…Read more
  •  127
    The phase rule and the notion of substance
    In Henk W. De Regt, Stephan Hartmann & Samir Okasha (eds.), EPSA Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009, Springer. pp. 253-62. 2011.
    In response to difficulties in understanding the notion of chemical substance at issue in Gibbs’ phase rule, there is a long tradition of reformulating the simple statement of the rule. The leading idea is to rewrite the rule with a term for the number of substances actually present and to introduce additional terms making explicit the various kinds of restrictions which in the original formulation are taken to be incorporated into Gibbs’ notion of the number of independent substances. Although …Read more
  •  126
    Reduction and emergence: a critique of Kim
    Philosophical Studies 146 (1): 93-116. 2009.
    In a recent critique of the doctrine of emergentism championed by its classic advocates up to C. D. Broad, Jaegwon Kim (Philosophical Studies 63:31–47, 1999) challenges their view about its applicability to the sciences and proposes a new account of how the opposing notion of reduction should be understood. Kim is critical of the classic conception advanced by Nagel and uses his new account in his criticism of emergentism. I question his claims about the successful reduction achieved in the scie…Read more
  •  112
    The discovery that water is H2O
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 16 (3). 2002.
    What are the criteria determining the individuation of chemical kinds? Recent philosophical discussion, which puts too much emphasis on microstructure, seems to presuppose a reductionist conception not motivated by the scientific facts. The present article traces the development of the traditional notion of a substance with the rise of modern chemistry from the end of the 18th century with a view to correcting this speculative distortion.
  •  198
    Process and Change: From a Thermodynamic Perspective
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 64 (2): 395-422. 2013.
    The creators of equilibrium and irreversible thermodynamics developed a conception of processes which bears on metaphysical discussions of change, occurrents, and continuants and merits the attention of contemporary analytic metaphysicians. It concerns the macroscopic domain, from which metaphysicians normally take their examples, and is unjustly ignored on the grounds that it is not ‘fundamental science’. Why this often-voiced view should disqualify just thermodynamics, and not the broad range …Read more