•  106
    Humean chance: Five questions for David Lewis (review)
    Erkenntnis 49 (3): 321-335. 1998.
    David Lewis's approach to objective chance is doubly distinctive. On the one hand, Lewis uses an epistemic principle to disclose the nature of chance. One the other, Lewis conjoins realism about chance with a reductive Humean metaphysics. I aim to undermine both aspects of his view. Specifically, I argue that reductive Humeanism fails across the board, and I use my discussion of chance to explain why. I also argue Lewis's "best-systems" approach to chance fails his own criteria for a metaphysics…Read more
  •  44
    Conditional Belief and the Ramsey Test
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 51 215-232. 2002.
    Consider the frame S believes that—. Fill it with a conditional, say If you eat an Apple, you'll drink a Coke. what makes the result true? More generally, what facts are marked by instances of S believes ? In a sense the answer is obious: beliefs are so marked. Yet that bromide leads directly to competing schools of thought. And the reason is simple. Common-sense thinks of belief two ways. Sometimes it sees it as a three-part affair. When so viewed either you believe, disbelieve, or suspend judg…Read more
  •  140
    Stalnaker on sensuous knowledge
    Philosophical Studies 137 (2). 2008.
    Robert Stalnaker has recently argued that a pair of natural thoughts are incompatible. One of them is the view that items of non-indexical factual knowledge rule out possibilities. The other is the view that knowing what sensuous experience is like involves non-indexical knowledge of its phenomenal character. I argue against Stalnaker’s take on things, elucidating along the way how our knowledge of what experience is like fits together with the natural idea that items of non-indexical factual kn…Read more
  •  21
    Modal infallibilism and basic truth
    In Fraser MacBride (ed.), Identity and Modality, Oxford University Press. pp. 40. 2006.
  •  156
    Belief, Reason & Logic
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 64 89-100. 2009.
  •  136
    Truth in Epistemology
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (1): 99-108. 1991.
  •  183
    Pollock on defeasible reasons
    Philosophical Studies (1): 1-14. 2012.
  • Having Reason in Mind
    Dissertation, The University of Arizona. 1991.
    The project consists of a defense of the reductivist program generally and an application of the program to the theory of epistemic justification. ;Chapter One sets out the problem of reducing justification to other terms and defends the legitimacy of this problem against attacks by Quine in particular and supervenience theorists generally. Chapter Two is an explication and refutation of all possible theories which reduce justification-facts to facts about the reliability of cognitive processes.…Read more
  •  139
    Conceptual gaps and odd possibilities
    Mind 108 (430): 377-380. 1999.
    Scott Sturgeon has claimed to undermine the principal argument for Physicalism, in his words, the view that ’actuality is exhausted by physical reality’. In noting that actuality is exhausted by physical reality, the Physicalist is not claiming that all that there is in actuality are those things identified by physics. Rather the thought is that actuality is made up of all the things identified by physics and anything which is a compound of these things. So there are tables as well as their micr…Read more
  •  749
    The Tale of Bella and Creda
    Philosophers' Imprint 15. 2015.
    Some philosophers defend the view that epistemic agents believe by lending credence. Others defend the view that such agents lend credence by believing. It can strongly appear that the disagreement between them is notational, that nothing of substance turns on whether we are agents of one sort or the other. But that is demonstrably not so. Only one of these types of epistemic agent, at most, could manifest a human-like configuration of attitudes; and it turns out that not both types of agent are…Read more