•  206
    The quantum counter-revolution: Internal conflicts in scientific change
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 26 (2): 121-136. 1995.
    Many of the experiments that produced the empirical basis of quantum mechanics relied on classical assumptions that contradicted quantum mechanics. Historically this did not cause practical problems, as classical mechanics was used mostly when it did not happen to diverge too much from quantum mechanics in the quantitative sense. That fortunate circumstances, however, did not alleviate the conceptual problems involved in understanding the classical experimental reasoning in quantum-mechanical te…Read more
  •  137
    A misunderstood rebellion
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 24 (5): 741-790. 1992.
  •  302
    Scientific Progress: Beyond Foundationalism and Coherentism
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 61 1-20. 2007.
    Scientific progress remains one of the most significant issues in the philosophy of science today. This is not only because of the intrinsic importance of the topic, but also because of its immense difficulty. In what sense exactly does science makes progress, and how is it that scientists are apparently able to achieve it better than people in other realms of human intellectual endeavour? Neither philosophers nor scientists themselves have been able to answer these questions to general satisfac…Read more
  •  187
    Is Water H2O? Evidence, Realism and Pluralism
    Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science. 2012.
    This book exhibits deep philosophical quandaries and intricacies of the historical development of science lying behind a simple and fundamental item of common sense in modern science, namely the composition of water as H2O. Three main phases of development are critically re-examined, covering the historical period from the 1760s to the 1860s: the Chemical Revolution, early electrochemistry, and early atomic chemistry. In each case, the author concludes that the empirical evidence available at th…Read more
  •  168
    Historians often feel that standard philosophical doctrines about the nature and development of science are not adequate for representing the real history of science. However, when philosophers of science fail to make sense of certain historical events, it is also possible that there is something wrong with the standard historical descriptions of those events, precluding any sensible explanation. If so, philosophical failure can be useful as a guide for improving historiography, and this constit…Read more
  •  4
    Editorial
    with Jon Agar and Joe Cain
    British Journal for the History of Science 42 (3): 319. 2009.
  •  68
    On the applicability of the quantum measurement formalism
    Erkenntnis 46 (2): 143-163. 1997.
    Customary discussions of quantum measurements are unrealistic, in the sense that they do not reflect what happens in most actual measurements even under ideal circumstances. Even theories of measurement which discard the projection postulate tend to retain two unrealistic assumptions of the von Neumann theory: that a measurement consists of a single physical interaction, and that the topic of every measurement is information wholly contained in the quantum state of the object of measurement. I s…Read more
  •  168
    How to take realism beyond foot-stamping
    Philosophy 76 (1): 5-30. 2001.
    I propose a reformulation of realism, as the pursuit of ontological plausibility in our systems of knowledge. This is dubbed plausibility realism, for convenience of reference. Plausibility realism is non-empiricist, in the sense that it uses ontological plausibility as an independent criterion from empirical adequacy in evaluating systems of knowledge. Ontological plausibility is conceived as a precondition for intelligibility, nor for Truth; therefore, the function of plausibilty realism is to…Read more
  •  34
    Complementary Science
    The Philosophers' Magazine 40 17-24. 2008.
  •  36
  •  2
    Measurement and the Disunity of Quantum Physics
    Dissertation, Stanford University. 1993.
    I present philosophical reflections arising from a study of laboratory measurement methods in quantum physics. More specifically, I investigate three major methods of measuring kinetic energy, from the period during which quantum physics was developed and came to be widely accepted: magnetic deflection, electrostatic retardation, and material retardation. The historical material serves as a provocative focus at which many broader philosophical topics come together: the empirical testing of theor…Read more
  •  3
  •  275
    We argue against the common view that it is impossible to give a causal account of the distant correlations that are revealed in EPR-type experiments. We take a realistic attitude about quantum mechanics which implies a willingness to modify our familiar concepts according to its teachings. We object to the argument that the violation of factorizability in EPR rules out causal accounts, since such an argument is at best based on the desire to retain a classical description of nature that consist…Read more
  •  282
    The Philosophical Grammar of Scientific Practice
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 25 (3): 205-221. 2011.
    I seek to provide a systematic and comprehensive framework for the description and analysis of scientific practice—a philosophical grammar of scientific practice, ‘grammar’ as meant by the later Wittgenstein. I begin with the recognition that all scientific work, including pure theorizing, consists of actions, of the physical, mental, and ‘paper-and-pencil’ varieties. When we set out to see what it is that one actually does in scientific work, the following set of questions naturally emerge: who…Read more
  •  1101
    Sensory Measurements: Coordination and Standardization
    Biological Theory 10 (3): 200-211. 2015.
    Do sensory measurements deserve the label of “measurement”? We argue that they do. They fit with an epistemological view of measurement held in current philosophy of science, and they face the same kinds of epistemological challenges as physical measurements do: the problem of coordination and the problem of standardization. These problems are addressed through the process of “epistemic iteration,” for all measurements. We also argue for distinguishing the problem of standardization from the pro…Read more
  •  337
    Preservative realism and its discontents: Revisiting caloric
    Philosophy of Science 70 (5): 902-912. 2003.
    A popular and plausible response against Laudan's “pessimistic induction” has been what I call “preservative realism,” which argues that there have actually been enough elements of scientific knowledge preserved through major theory‐change processes, and that those elements can be accepted realistically. This paper argues against preservative realism, in particular through a critical review of Psillos's argument concerning the case of the caloric theory of heat. Contrary to his argument, the his…Read more
  •  81
    Complementary Science
    The Philosophers' Magazine 40 (40): 17-24. 2008.
  •  74
    What the ravens really teach us : the intrinsic contextuality of evidence
    with Grant Fisher
    In Philip Dawid, William Twining & Mimi Vasilaki (eds.), Evidence, Inference and Enquiry, Oup/british Academy. 2011.
    This chapter advances a contextual view of evidence, through a reconsideration of Hempel's paradox of confirmation. The initial view regarding Hempel's paradox is that a non-black non-raven does confirm ‘All ravens are black’, but only in certain contexts. The chapter begins by reformulating the paradox as a puzzle about how the same entity can have variable evidential values for a given proposition. It then offers a three-stage solution to the reformulated paradox. The situation makes better se…Read more
  •  96
    Acidity: The Persistence of the Everyday in the Scientific
    Philosophy of Science 79 (5): 690-700. 2012.
    Acidity provides an interesting example of an everyday concept that developed fully into a scientific one; it is one of the oldest concepts in chemistry and remains an important one. However, up to now there has been no unity to it. Currently two standard theoretical definitions coexist ; the standard laboratory measure of acidity, namely the pH, only corresponds directly to the Br⊘nsted-Lowry concept. The lasting identity of the acidity concept in modern chemistry is based on the persistence of…Read more
  •  12
    Seeking ultimates: an intuitive guide to physics
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 33 (2): 368-371. 2002.
  •  202
    Operationalism
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2009.
  •  77
    Circularity and reliability in measurement
    Perspectives on Science 3 (2): 153-172. 1995.
    The direct use of a physical law for the purpose of measurement creates a problem of circularity: the law needs to be empirically tested in order to ensure the reliability of measurement, but the testing requires that we already know the value of the quantity to be measured. This problem is discussed through some detailed examples of energy measurements in quantum physics; three major methods are analyzed in their interrelation, with a focus on the method of “material retardation.” It seems that…Read more
  •  247
    Why do some epistemic objects persist despite undergoing serious changes, while others go extinct in similar situations? Scientists have often been careless in deciding which epistemic objects to retain and which ones to eliminate; historians and philosophers of science have been on the whole much too unreflective in accepting the scientists’ decisions in this regard. Through a re-examination of the history of oxygen and phlogiston, I will illustrate the benefits to be gained from challenging an…Read more
  •  225
    I develop a concept of observability that pertains to qualities rather than objects: a quality is observable if it can be registered by human sensation (possibly with the aid of instruments) without involving optional interpretations. This concept supports a better description of observations in science and everyday life than the object-based observability concepts presupposing causal information-transfer from the object to the observer. It also allows a rehabilitation of the traditional empiric…Read more