• Lyons, D., "Ethics and the Rule of Law" (review)
    Mind 94 (n/a): 163. 1985.
  •  18
    Voluntary Obligations and Normative Powers
    with Neil MacCormick
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 46 (1): 59-102. 1972.
  •  210
    The trouble with particularism (Dancy's version) (review)
    Mind 115 (457): 99-120. 2006.
  •  240
    Rights and Individual Well-Being
    Ratio Juris 5 (2): 127-142. 1992.
    This article challenges the view permeating much philosophical thought that the primacy of individual rights represents the individual's standpoint against the public good or against the requirements of others generally. The author explicates the underlying features of our common culture contending that the conflict between individual and general good as being central to rights misconstrues the surface features of rights. The range and nature of common goods determine the options available to in…Read more
  •  6
    Law, Morality and Society
    Philosophical Quarterly 28 (111): 181-182. 1978.
  •  69
    The practice of value - reply
    In Jay Wallace (ed.), The Practice of Value, Oxford University Press. 2003.
    The privilege of having three sets of extensive and hard-hitting comments on one's work is as welcome as it is rare, and especially so on this occasion as the lectures were, for me, but thefirst (well, not entirely first) stab at a subject I hope to explore at greater length. The reflectionsthat follow will respond to some of the criticisms, but will not be a point by point reply. I will use the occasion to clarify some obscurities in the lectures, and to contrast my view with some of my critics…Read more
  •  93
    Human agents act for reasons that contribute to their good. However, in our explanation of why agents act for reasons that depend on what they value, we encounter the problem of situations in which goods are neither better than others nor are of equal value. The incommensurability of value can then be seen to lead to an incommensurability of reasons for action. Examining rationalist and classical conceptions of human agency, Raz uses the presence of incommensurability to understand how this affe…Read more
  •  69
    Principles of equality
    Mind 87 (347): 321-342. 1978.
  •  156
    The claims of reflective equilibrium
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 25 (3). 1982.
  •  2
    Formalism and the Rule of law
    In Robert P. George (ed.), Natural law theory: contemporary essays, Oxford University Press. pp. 309--340. 1992.
  •  177
    Professor Robert Alexy wrote a book whose avowed purpose is to refute the basic tenets of a type of legal theory which 'has long since been obsolete in legal science and practice'. The quotation is from the German Federal Constitutional Court in 1968. The fact that Prof Alexy himself mentions no writings in the legal positivist tradition [in English] later than Hart's The Concept of Law (1961) may suggest that he shares the court's view. The book itself may be evidence to the contrary. After all…Read more
  •  231
    Can there be a theory of law?
    In Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory, Blackwell. 2004.
    The paper deals with the possibility of a theory of the nature of law as such, a theory which will be necessarily true of all law. It explores the relations between explanations of concepts and of the things they are concepts of, the possibility that the law has essential properties, and the possibility that the law changes its nature over time, and that what is law at a given place and time depends on the culture and concepts of that place and time. It also considers the possibility of understa…Read more
  •  30
    The Authority of Law
    with Alan R. White
    Philosophical Quarterly 30 (120): 278. 1980.
  •  1
    Multikulturalismus: eine liberale Perspektive: I. Liberalismus und Multikulturalismus
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 43 (2): 307-328. 1995.
  •  45
    Sorensen: Vagueness has no function in law
    Legal Theory 7 (4): 417-419. 2001.
    There is much in the paper that I agree with, much that I do not understand and am probably not competent to understand, and some which I am puzzled by. I will concentrate on the last. Both regarding puzzles, and regarding points of agreement and incomprehension, I will be selective and touch on only a few.
  •  634
    Authority and justification
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1): 3-29. 1985.
    an account of the nature of authority
  •  3
    Value, Respect, and Attachment
    Cambridge University Press. 2001.
    The book is a contribution to the study of values, as they affect both our personal and our public life. It defends the view that values are necessarily universal, on the ground that that is a condition of their intelligibility. It does, however, reject most common conceptions of universality, like those embodied in the writings on human rights. It aims to reconcile the universality of value with the social dependence of value and the centrality to our life of deep attachments to people and coun…Read more
  •  133
    I will say something on two or three related but distinct topics. First, something on the grounding of normative beliefs, a topic – as I see it – in moral epistemology, and then after a brief remark on explanation, something against a certain understanding of basic principles. My observations were prompted by reflection on Jerry’s desire to rescue justice from the facts.
  •  67
    Review of Walzer on morality as interpretation
  •  244
    The role of well‐being
    Philosophical Perspectives 18 (1). 2004.
    "Well-being" signifies the good life, the life which is good for the person whose life it is. I have argued that well-being consists in a wholehearted and successful pursuit of valuable relationships and goals. This view, a little modified, is defended , but the main aim of the article is to consider the role of well-being in practical thought. In particular I will examine a suggestion which says that when we care about people, and when we ought to care about people, what we do, or ought to, car…Read more
  •  1
    La autoridad del derecho: ensayos sobre derecho y moral
    with Rolando E. Tamayo Y. Salmorán
    Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas. 1985.
  •  33
    Practical reasoning (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 1978.
  •  107
    If promises are binding there must be a reason to do as one promised. The paper is motivated by belief that there is a difficulty in explaining what that reason is. It arises because the reasons that promising creates are content-independent. Similar difficulties arise regarding other content-independent reasons, though their solution need not be the same. Section One introduces an approach to promises, and outlines an account of them that I have presented before. It forms the backdrop for the …Read more
  •  680
    The Morality of Freedom
    Oxford University Press. 1986.
    Ranging over central issues of morals and politics and the nature of freedom and authority, this study examines the role of value-neutrality, rights, equality, ...
  •  55
    H. L. A. Hart : Joseph Raz
    Utilitas 5 (2): 145-156. 1993.
  •  230
    On the value of distributional equality
    In Stephen De Wijze, Matthew H. Kramer & Ian Carter (eds.), Hillel Steiner and the Anatomy of Justice: Themes and Challenges, Routledge. 2009.
    The paper returns to the question whether equality in distribution is valuable in itself, or, if you like, whether it is intrinsically valuable. Its bulk is an examination of two familiar arguments against the intrinsic value of distributional equality: the levelling down objection and the objection that equality violates some person-affecting condition, in that its realisation does not improve the lot of people.
  •  105
    The central conflict: morality and self-interest
    In Roger Crisp & Brad Hooker (eds.), Well-Being and Morality: Essays in Honour of James Griffin, Clarendon Press. pp. 209--238. 2000.
    Self‐sacrifice does not necessarily involve conflict between morality and self‐interest, and when making sacrifices we do not necessarily harm our self‐interest. While people may reasonably care about their own well‐being, a person's well‐being is not, for that person, a source of value or reasons for action. People act for reasons, i.e. for what appears to them to be adequate reasons, regardless of whether or not they serve their well‐being. Sometimes, the reasons that appear to be conclusive, …Read more
  • El Problema de la Naturaleza del Derecho
    Isonomía. Revista de Teoría y Filosofía Del Derecho 3 (20-21). 1995.