•  34
    Summary In his Theoremata de lumine, et umbre (1521), Francesco Maurolyco (1494–1575) discussed, inter alia, the problem of the pinhole camera. Maurolyco outlined a framework based on Euclidean geometry in which he applied the rectilinear propagation of light to the casting of shadow on a screen behind a pinhole. We limit our discussion to the problem of how the image behind an aperture is formed, and follow the way Maurolyco combined theory with instrument to solve the problem of the projection…Read more
  •  7
    The Modeling of Nature (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 36 (1): 338-340. 2004.
  •  54
    The year 2009 marks the 400th anniversary of the publication of one of the most revolutionary scientific texts ever written. In this book, appropriately entitled, Astronomia nova, Johannes Kepler developed an astronomical theory which departs fundamentally from the systems of Ptolemy and Copernicus. One of the great innovations of this theory is its dependence on the science of optics. The declared goal of Kepler in his earlier publication, Paralipomena to Witelo whereby The Optical Part of Astr…Read more
  •  38
    Book reviews (review)
    with R. S. Woolhouse, George N. Schlesinger, Lawrence Udell Fike, Lila Luce, Ruth Weintraub, and Mark Rowlands
    Philosophia 22 (3-4): 293-296. 1993.
  •  54
    Histories of kinematics and Einstein’s relativity theory: A collage of historiographies Content Type Journal Article Pages 1-4 DOI 10.1007/s11016-011-9532-6 Authors Giora Hon, Department of Philosophy, University of Haifa, 31905 Haifa, Israel Journal Metascience Online ISSN 1467-9981 Print ISSN 0815-0796.
  •  4
    Book reviews (review)
    with R. S. Woolhouse, George N. Schlesinger, Lawrence Udell Fike, Lila Luce, Ruth Weintraub, and Mark Rowlands
    Philosophia 22 (3-4): 425-460. 1993.
  •  1174
    Summary We offer a novel historical-philosophical framework for discussing experimental practice which we call ‘Generating Experimental Knowledge’. It combines three different perspectives: experimental systems, concept formation, and the pivotal role of error. We then present an historical account of the invention of the Scanning Tunnelling Microscope (STM), or Raster-Tunnelmikroskop, and interpret it within the proposed framework. We show that at the outset of the STM project, Binnig and Rohre…Read more
  •  60
    Can Error Imply Existence?
    with Rami Raveh
    Philosophy and Theology 18 (2): 201-218. 2006.
    Descartes’s Cogito, “I am thinking, therefore I exist,” is perhaps the most famous assertion in the history of philosophy. Thirteen hundred years earlier, St. Augustine formulated a similar claim, arguing “if I am mistaken, I am.” Did St. Augustine anticipate Descartes? We show that Descartes’s dictum is a novel insight and less vulnerable to criticism than the claim of St. Augustine. Whereas Descartes searched for one true proposition on which he could base scientificknowledge, St. Augustine so…Read more
  •  453
    Is There a Concept of Experimental Error in Greek Astronomy?
    British Journal for the History of Science 22 (2): 129-150. 1989.
    The attempt to narrow the general discourse of the problem of error and to focus it on the specific problem of experimental error may be approached from different directions. One possibility is to establish a focusing process from the standpoint of history; such an approach requires a careful scrutiny of the history of science with a view to identifying the juncture when the problem of experimental error was properly understood and accounted for. In a study of this kind one would have to examine…Read more
  •  18
    The Modeling of Nature (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 36 (1): 338-340. 2004.
  •  56
    Maxwell’s contrived analogy: An early version of the methodology of modeling
    with Bernard R. Goldstein
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 43 (4): 236-257. 2012.
    The term “analogy” stands for a variety of methodological practices all related in one way or another to the idea of proportionality. We claim that in his first substantial contribution to electromagnetism James Clerk Maxwell developed a methodology of analogy which was completely new at the time or, to borrow John North’s expression, Maxwell’s methodology was a “newly contrived analogue”. In his initial response to Michael Faraday’s experimental researches in electromagnetism, Maxwell did not s…Read more
  •  41
    Symmetry and asymmetry in electrodynamics from Rowland to Einstein
    with Bernard R. Goldstein
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 37 (4): 635-660. 2006.
  •  97
    The unnatural nature of the laws of Nature: Symmetry and asymmetry.
    In S. French & H. Kamminga (eds.), Correspondence, Invariance and Heuristics, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 171--187. 1993.
  •  430
    Towards a Typology of Experimental Errors: an Epistemological View
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20 (4): 469. 1989.
    This paper is concerned with the problem of experimental error. The prevalent view that experimental errors can be dismissed as a tiresome but trivial blemish on the method of experimentation is criticized. It is stressed that the occurrence of errors in experiments constitutes a permanent feature of the attempt to test theories in the physical world, and this feature deserves proper attention. It is suggested that a classification of types of experimental error may be useful as a heuristic devi…Read more
  •  32
    The year 2009 marks the 400th anniversary of the publication of one of the most revolutionary scientific texts ever written. In this book, appropriately entitled, Astronomia nova, Johannes Kepler developed an astronomical theory which departs fundamentally from the systems of Ptolemy and Copernicus. One of the great innovations of this theory is its dependence on the science of optics. The declared goal of Kepler in his earlier publication, Paralipomena to Witelo whereby The Optical Part of Astr…Read more
  •  39
    The idea that nature is governed by laws and that the goal of science is to discover and formulate these laws, rose to prominence during the Scientific Revolution of the seventeenth century. It was manifestly held by the most significant actors of that revolution such as Galileo, Descartes, Kepler, Boyle, and Newton. But this idea was not new. In fact, it made an appearance in the Middle Ages, and it is likely to have emerged already in Antiquity.1In this paper we pay close attention to the conc…Read more
  •  31
    On Kepler's awareness of the problem of experimental error
    Annals of Science 44 (6): 545-591. 1987.
    SummaryThis paper is an account of Kepler's explicit awareness of the problem of experimental error. As a study of the Astronomia nova shows, Kepler exploited his awareness of the occurrences of experimental errors to guide him to the right conclusion. Errors were thus employed, so to speak, perhaps for the first time, to bring about a major physical discovery: Kepler's laws of planetary motion. ‘Know then’, to use Kepler's own words, ‘that errors show us the way to truth.’ With a survey of Kepl…Read more
  •  337
    A critical note on J. S. mill's classification of fallacies
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42 (2): 263-268. 1991.
  •  3
    Explanation (edited book)
    with S. Rakover
    Springer Verlag. 2001.
  •  45
    Unpacking "For Reasons of Symmetry": Two Categories of Symmetry Arguments
    with Bernard R. Goldstein
    Philosophy of Science 73 (4): 419-439. 2006.
    Hermann Weyl succeeded in presenting a consistent overarching analysis that accounts for symmetry in material artifacts, natural phenomena, and physical theories. Weyl showed that group theory is the underlying mathematical structure for symmetry in all three domains. But in this study Weyl did not include appeals to symmetry arguments which, for example, Einstein expressed as “for reasons of symmetry”. An argument typically takes the form of a set of premises and rules of inference that lead to…Read more
  •  302
    Can the monster errour be slain?
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 5 (3). 1991.
    Abstract One cannot discount experimental errors and turn the attention to the logicomathematical structure of a physical theory without distorting the nature of the scientific method. The occurrence of errors in experiments constitutes an inherent feature of the attempt to test theories in the physical world. This feature deserves proper attention which has been neglected. An attempt is made to address this problem
  •  13
    Does a Living System Have a State?
    In A. Rojszczak, J. Cachro & G. Kurczewski (eds.), Philosophical Dimensions of Logic and Science, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 139--150. 2003.
  •  50
    Kepler's move from
    with Bernard R. Goldstein
    Perspectives on Science 13 (1): 74-111. 2005.
    : This study of the concept of orbit is intended to throw light on the nature of revolutionary concepts in science. We observe that Kepler transformed theoretical astronomy that was understood in terms of orbs [Latin: orbes] (spherical shells to which the planets were attached) and models (called hypotheses at the time), by introducing a single term, orbit [Latin: orbita], that is, the path of a planet in space resulting from the action of physical causes expressed in laws of nature. To demonstr…Read more