•  194
    The puzzle of true blue
    Analysis 66 (3): 173-178. 2006.
    Most men and nearly all women have non-defective colour vision, as measured by standard colour tests such as those of Ishihara and Farns- worth. But people vary, according to gender, race and age in their per- formance in matching experiments. For example, when subjects are shown a screen, one half of which is lit by a mixture of red and green lights and the other by yellow or orange light, and they are asked to ad- just the mixture of lights so as to make the two halves of the screen match in c…Read more
  •  35
    Phenomenal consciousness and cognitive accessibility
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6): 527-528. 2007.
    Block tries to show that the results of the Sperling experiment lend support to the view that phenomenology outstrips cognitive accessibility. I argue that Block fails to make a compelling case for this general claim on the basis of the Sperling data
  •  104
    True blue redux
    Analysis 67 (1): 92-93. 2007.
    A chip looks true blue to John and greenish blue to Jane. On the face of it, at least one of the two perceivers has an inaccurate colour experience; for the chip cannot be both true blue and greenish blue. But John and Jane are “normal” perceivers, and there is no privileged class of normal perceivers (Block 1999). This is the puzzle of true blue (Tye
  •  150
  •  186
    Consciousness, color, and content
    Philosophical Studies 113 (3): 233-235. 2003.
  •  136
    Naturalism and the problem of intentionality
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1): 122-42. 1994.
  •  37
    Response to Discussants (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (3): 679-687. 1998.
  •  86
    Blindsight, orgasm, and representational overlap
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 268-269. 1995.
    It is argued that there is no fallacy in the reasoning in the example of the thirsty blindsight subject, on one reconstruction of that reasoning. Neither the case of orgasm nor the case of a visual versus an auditory experience as of something overheard shows that phenomenal content is not representational.
  •  173
    Up close with the speckled hen
    Analysis 70 (2): 283-286. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation).
  •  164
  •  153
    Reflections on Dennett and consciousness (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (4): 891-6. 1993.
  •  468
    Absent qualia and the mind-body problem
    Philosophical Review 115 (2): 139-168. 2006.
    At the very heart of the mind-body problem is the question of the nature of consciousness. It is consciousness, and in particular _phenomenal_ consciousness, that makes the mind-body relation so deeply perplexing. Many philosophers hold that no defi nition of phenomenal consciousness is possible: any such putative defi nition would automatically use the concept of phenomenal consciousness and thus render the defi nition circular. The usual view is that the concept of phenomenal consciousness is …Read more
  •  63
    The puzzle of Hesperus and Phosphorus
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 56 (3). 1978.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  133
    Seven Puzzles of Thought and How to Solve Them: An Originalist Theory of Concepts
    with Richard Mark Sainsbury
    Oxford University Press. 2012.
    Sainsbury and Tye present a new theory, 'originalism', which provides natural, simple solutions to puzzles about thought that have troubled philosophers for centuries. They argue that concepts are to be individuated by their origin, rather than epistemically or semantically. Although thought is special, no special mystery attaches to its nature.
  •  141
  •  93
    Is consciousness vague or arbitrary?
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (3): 679-685. 1996.
  •  1370
    Intentionalism and the Argument from No Common Content
    Philosophical Perspectives 21 (1): 589-613. 2007.
    Disjunctivists (Hinton 1973, Snowdon 1990, Martin 2002, 2006) often motivate their approach to perceptual experience by appealing in part to the claim that in cases of veridical perception, the subject is directly in contact with the perceived object. When I perceive a table, for example, there is no table-like sense-impression that stands as an intermediary between the table and me. Nor am I related to the table as I am to a deer when I see its footprint in the snow. I do not experience the tab…Read more
  •  276
    Oh Yes It Is
    Mind 110 (439): 695-697. 2001.
  •  260
    The admissible contents of visual experience
    Philosophical Quarterly 59 (236): 541-562. 2009.
    My purpose is to take a close look at the nature of visual content. I discuss the view that visual experiences have only existential contents, the view that visual experiences have either singular or gappy contents, and the view that visual experiences have multiple contents. I also consider a proposal about visual content inspired by Kaplan's well known theory of indexicals. I draw out some consequences of my discussion for the thesis of intentionalism with respect to the phenomenal character o…Read more
  •  12
    New troubles for the qualia freak
    In Brian P. McLaughlin & Jonathan D. Cohen (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell. 2007.
    The phenomenal character of an experience is what it is like subjectively to undergo the experience. Experiences vary in their phenomenal character, in what it is like to un- dergo them. Think, for example of the subjective differences between feeling a burning pain in a toe, experiencing an itch in an arm, smelling rotten eggs, tasting Marmite, having a visual experience of bright purple, running one’s fingers over rough sandpaper, feeling hungry, experiencing anger, feeling elated. Insofar as …Read more
  •  95
    Speaks on strong property representationalism
    Philosophical Studies 170 (1): 85-86. 2014.
    Strong property representationalism, as applied to visual experience, is the thesis that the phenomenal character of a visual experience is one and the same as the property complex or ‘sensible profile’ represented by that experience. Speaks discusses the following argument against this thesis:Let ‘RED’ stand for the phenomenal character of the experience of red.(1) Red = RED (strong property representationalism).(2) My pen has no representational properties, but is red.Hence,(3) My pen has a ph…Read more
  •  105
    Blindsight, the absent qualia hypothesis, and the mystery of consciousness
    In Christopher Hookway (ed.), Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, Cambridge University Press. pp. 19-40. 1993.
    One standard objection to the view that phenomenal experience is functionally determined is based upon what has come to be called ‘The Absent Qualia Hypothesis’, the idea that there could be a person or a machine that was functionally exactly like us but that felt or consciously experienced nothing at all . Advocates of this hypothesis typically maintain that we can easily imagine possible systems that meet the appropriate functional specifications but that intuitively lack any phenomenal consci…Read more